A Strawsonian Objection to Russell s Theory of Descriptions

Similar documents
THE USE OF ENGLISH MOVIE IN TEACHING AUSTIN S ACT

Anglia Ruskin University Assessment Offences

University of Huddersfield Repository

Practice Examination IREB

Build on students informal understanding of sharing and proportionality to develop initial fraction concepts.

The Enterprise Knowledge Portal: The Concept

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

Writing Research Articles

5. UPPER INTERMEDIATE

Thought and Suggestions on Teaching Material Management Job in Colleges and Universities Based on Improvement of Innovation Capacity

Rule-based Expert Systems

Scientific Method Investigation of Plant Seed Germination

Residential Admissions Procedure Manual

The Singapore Copyright Act applies to the use of this document.

TUCSON CAMPUS SCHOOL OF BUSINESS SYLLABUS

CONSTRUCTION OF AN ACHIEVEMENT TEST Introduction One of the important duties of a teacher is to observe the student in the classroom, laboratory and

Effective practices of peer mentors in an undergraduate writing intensive course

MANAGERIAL LEADERSHIP

NCEO Technical Report 27

Gricean Communication and Transmission of Thoughts

Systematic reviews in theory and practice for library and information studies

ACADEMIC POLICIES AND PROCEDURES

Understanding the Relationship between Comprehension and Production

November 2012 MUET (800)

HISTORY COURSE WORK GUIDE 1. LECTURES, TUTORIALS AND ASSESSMENT 2. GRADES/MARKS SCHEDULE

The Effect of Extensive Reading on Developing the Grammatical. Accuracy of the EFL Freshmen at Al Al-Bayt University

Shared Content (Draft)

Thesis-Proposal Outline/Template

HDR Presentation of Thesis Procedures pro-030 Version: 2.01

K-12 PROFESSIONAL DEVELOPMENT

Division Strategies: Partial Quotients. Fold-Up & Practice Resource for. Students, Parents. and Teachers

THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO. Department of Psychology

Rule Learning With Negation: Issues Regarding Effectiveness

Effect of Cognitive Apprenticeship Instructional Method on Auto-Mechanics Students

Classroom Assessment Techniques (CATs; Angelo & Cross, 1993)

Audit Documentation. This redrafted SSA 230 supersedes the SSA of the same title in April 2008.

The Foundations of Interpersonal Communication

The University of British Columbia Board of Governors

STANISLAUS COUNTY CIVIL GRAND JURY CASE #08-04 LA GRANGE ELEMENTARY SCHOOL DISTRICT

Digital Media Literacy

Exploring Persona-Scenarios - Using Storytelling to Create Design Ideas

Lymphedema Advocacy Group

Math Hunt th November, Sodalitas de Mathematica St. Xavier s College, Maitighar Kathmandu, Nepal

The Implementation of Interactive Multimedia Learning Materials in Teaching Listening Skills

Possessive have and (have) got in New Zealand English Heidi Quinn, University of Canterbury, New Zealand

Tutoring First-Year Writing Students at UNM

Rubric for Scoring English 1 Unit 1, Rhetorical Analysis

BIOH : Principles of Medical Physiology

SCHEMA ACTIVATION IN MEMORY FOR PROSE 1. Michael A. R. Townsend State University of New York at Albany

Arizona s English Language Arts Standards th Grade ARIZONA DEPARTMENT OF EDUCATION HIGH ACADEMIC STANDARDS FOR STUDENTS

An Education Newsletter from the Attorneys of Rosenstein, Fist & Ringold 2017 Issue 6

b) Allegation means information in any form forwarded to a Dean relating to possible Misconduct in Scholarly Activity.

Developing a Language for Assessing Creativity: a taxonomy to support student learning and assessment

Mental Models and the Meaning of Connectives: A Study on Children, Adolescents and Adults

MKTG 611- Marketing Management The Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Fall 2016

Economics 100: Introduction to Macroeconomics Spring 2012, Tuesdays and Thursdays Kenyon 134

University of Michigan - Flint POLICY ON FACULTY CONFLICTS OF INTEREST AND CONFLICTS OF COMMITMENT

REGULATIONS RELATING TO ADMISSION, STUDIES AND EXAMINATION AT THE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF SOUTHEAST NORWAY

UC Santa Cruz Graduate Research Symposium 2016

Abstractions and the Brain

The Effect of Discourse Markers on the Speaking Production of EFL Students. Iman Moradimanesh

A Case-Based Approach To Imitation Learning in Robotic Agents

CRITICAL THINKING AND WRITING: ENG 200H-D01 - Spring 2017 TR 10:45-12:15 p.m., HH 205

Welcome to the Purdue OWL. Where do I begin? General Strategies. Personalizing Proofreading

INTRODUCTION TO GENERAL PSYCHOLOGY (PSYC 1101) ONLINE SYLLABUS. Instructor: April Babb Crisp, M.S., LPC

Grade 6: Module 2A: Unit 2: Lesson 8 Mid-Unit 3 Assessment: Analyzing Structure and Theme in Stanza 4 of If

Last Editorial Change:

prehending general textbooks, but are unable to compensate these problems on the micro level in comprehending mathematical texts.

Analysis of Students Incorrect Answer on Two- Dimensional Shape Lesson Unit of the Third- Grade of a Primary School

Observing Teachers: The Mathematics Pedagogy of Quebec Francophone and Anglophone Teachers

2 nd grade Task 5 Half and Half

May 2011 (Revised March 2016)

ATW 202. Business Research Methods

The Extend of Adaptation Bloom's Taxonomy of Cognitive Domain In English Questions Included in General Secondary Exams

Focusing bound pronouns

PREDISPOSING FACTORS TOWARDS EXAMINATION MALPRACTICE AMONG STUDENTS IN LAGOS UNIVERSITIES: IMPLICATIONS FOR COUNSELLING

Does Linguistic Communication Rest on Inference?

PREP S SPEAKER LISTENER TECHNIQUE COACHING MANUAL

Reading Horizons. Organizing Reading Material into Thought Units to Enhance Comprehension. Kathleen C. Stevens APRIL 1983

Communicative Language Teaching (CLT): A Critical and Comparative Perspective

Individual Component Checklist L I S T E N I N G. for use with ONE task ENGLISH VERSION

Designed by Candie Donner

DESIGNPRINCIPLES RUBRIC 3.0

MADISON METROPOLITAN SCHOOL DISTRICT

A Game-based Assessment of Children s Choices to Seek Feedback and to Revise

Guidelines for Incorporating Publication into a Thesis. September, 2015

A Metacognitive Approach to Support Heuristic Solution of Mathematical Problems

4a: Reflecting on Teaching

Critical Thinking in Everyday Life: 9 Strategies

Showing synthesis in your writing and starting to develop your own voice

West s Paralegal Today The Legal Team at Work Third Edition

DICE - Final Report. Project Information Project Acronym DICE Project Title

User Guide. LSE for You: Graduate Course Choices. London School of Economics and Political Science Houghton Street, London WC2A 2AE

Helping Students Get to Where Ideas Can Find Them

Think A F R I C A when assessing speaking. C.E.F.R. Oral Assessment Criteria. Think A F R I C A - 1 -

TRAITS OF GOOD WRITING

IEP AMENDMENTS AND IEP CHANGES

Just in Time to Flip Your Classroom Nathaniel Lasry, Michael Dugdale & Elizabeth Charles

Transcription:

Article (Unspecified) Ramachandran, Murali (1993). Analysis, 53 (4). pp. 209-212. ISSN 00032638 This version is available from Sussex Research Online: http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/2272/ This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies and may differ from the published version or from the version of record. If you wish to cite this item you are advised to consult the publisher s version. Please see the URL above for details on accessing the published version. Copyright and reuse: Sussex Research Online is a digital repository of the research output of the University. Copyright and all moral rights to the version of the paper presented here belong to the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. To the extent reasonable and practicable, the material made available in SRO has been checked for eligibility before being made available. Copies of full text items generally can be reproduced, displayed or performed and given to third parties in any format or medium for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes without prior permission or charge, provided that the authors, title and full bibliographic details are credited, a hyperlink and/or URL is given for the original metadata page and the content is not changed in any way. http://sro.sussex.ac.uk

The gist of one of Strawson s by now, familiar objections [3] to Russell s theory of descriptions [2] is that a speaker may, quite naturally and correctly, utter a sentence of the form the F is G to talk about, and be understood as talking about, a particular F even when it is commonly known that there is more than one F. Yet, the objection continues, by Russell s theory (RTD) such an utterance would strictly speaking be false. Modern Russellians as is also well known weather the attack by pointing out that the context in which an incomplete (definite) description is normally used will furnish either (a) an adequate completion of the description or (b) an adequate delimitation of the domain of quantification. They come armed, moreover, with the Gricean distinction between expressed and intended propositions so that they can accommodate the intuition that utterances involving incomplete descriptions often convey object-dependent propositions. Since Strawson himself takes contextual features to aid the singling-out of objects when descriptions are used (see e.g. [3], pp. 21-22; [4], pp. 186-87), it would appear that these Russellian moves lead more or less to a stand off (see Neale [1] for a recent discussion). Not quite. Strawson sought to displace RTD by bringing to our consideration normal, but (allegedly) RTD-countervailing, uses of descriptions. Russellians have generally responded, not by challenging Strawson s estimation of the (kinds of) circumstances in which descriptions are normally used, i.e. his appraisal of what counts as a normal use, but by attempting to show that such uses actually square with a plausibly-embellished version of RTD. This leaves us with an alternative line of attack: that of furnishing abnormal uses of descriptions, i.e. uses which ordinary speakers of the language would consider unnatural or improper, but which in fact comply with RTD (embellished or not). 1

Let us begin by considering a (hypothetical) use of an incomplete description, the F, where the speaker does not have a particular F in mind, and where, to boot, the context does not suggest an adequate completion of the description or a sufficiently restrictive delimitation of the domain of quantification. Suppose that someone uttered (1) The table is covered with books. in a room containing numerous tables, many covered with books and many not, but with no specific table (or any other object, for that matter) in mind. In my opinion, we would find that utterance, call it t, unintelligible in the sense that we would feel unable to specify what it would take, what the world would have to be like, for that utterance to be true. 1 Of course, we might ask the speaker which table she was talking about; but after the response to the effect that she wasn t talking about any particular table, as the supposition demands, we surely would be at a loss as to how to take (interpret) t. However, if RTD were correct, t should be intelligible even though it is not contextually-complete. For, intuitively, an utterance in the same context of the Russellian paraphrase of (1), viz. (1a) There is exactly one table and whatever is a table is covered with books. would be intelligible, albeit manifestly false. The problem this poses for Russellians is clear. On their account these utterances would have the same 1 In denying that t is intelligible, I am not denying that the sentence-type of which it is a token, viz. (1), is meaningful in the sense Strawson takes sentences to be meaningful or significant ([6], pp. 9-10). For Strawson, a sentence s meaningfulness (significance) consists in its potential for being used to make true or false statements; clearly, (1) has this potential too. 2

content; but how, in that case, can the difference in intelligibility be explained? It seems that we do have a clash between RTD and ordinary language, as Strawson suggests. The likes of t thereby give rise to a stronger Strawsonian argument against RTD (as an account of natural-language descriptions). In its general form, it runs something like this. Utterances involving contextually-incomplete descriptions are unintelligible in that we have grave difficulty in ascertaining what is asserted in such cases. We would face no such difficulty if RTD were correct, however, for the quantificational paraphrases of these utterances validated by RTD aren t unintelligible in this sense. Hence, the Russellian account is not correct. It would be a mistake to see this objection as merely a variation of Strawson s point about the disparity between the verdict of ordinary language and RTD on a present-day utterance, k, of (2) The king of France is wise. According to Strawson, we that is, ordinary speakers would be disinclined to proclaim the utterance either as true or as false, and, indeed, it does follow from what I say that we would be similarly disinclined in the case of t. But, there is a significant point of disanalogy: our discomfort with t stems from our inability to interpret it, i.e. to determine its truth-conditions, whereas we have no such difficulty in the case of k. In contrast to t, we do know (or think we know) what it would take for k to be true or false France would have to have a (unique) king who was (or was not) wise. The newer objection therefore cuts deeper in my opinion. Some readers may find the objection unconvincing precisely because the alleged counterexamples to RTD involve abnormal uses of descriptions (and, consequently, abnormal speakers of the language). The following thought does seem compelling: that if a theory of content is to be challenged by way of 3

exposing a clash with ordinary language, one needs to provide normal, i.e. natural, examples; after all, the reasoning runs, no theory could be expected to account for abnormal uses these simply resist any standard analysis. This response misses the point however, or, rather, mislocates the clash. The utterer of t, for instance, is indeed an abnormal speaker in that she is using a description abnormally by our, that is ordinary speakers, lights. But, this is precisely what presents the problem for Russellians: as already noted, they owe an explanation of why it is that someone who uttered (1) in the envisaged circumstances would be regarded as abnormal, as having misused language, whereas someone who uttered (1a) would not be so regarded. In any case, the objection can be made without recourse to deviant uses or speakers. Suppose that in the envisaged ( many-table ) scenario we were asked to assess the correctness of certain sentences, among them (1) and (1a), which were generated by a computer and displayed on a screen (say). I venture that even in that situation we would be inclined to proclaim the token of (1a) as false but would experience as much difficulty in simply interpreting the token of (1), i.e. in determining its truth-conditions, as in the earlier example. So, we would have the same problem, but no actual deviant uses or users. 2 Another thought which might fuel reservations about the force of the objection is the thought that Russellians already have a perfectly adequate explanation of t s unintelligibility. Surely, it may be reasoned, the fact that it is manifestly false is quite sufficient to account for the difficulty we experience in interpreting t; it is only natural that we are highly reluctant to take the utterer as saying something which she clearly knows to be false. However, if this explanation were right, we would have no more difficulty in interpreting t than we would an utterance, in the same context, of the manifestly false (1a). But, intuitively, this just is not so. 2 I thank Peter Millican for suggesting something along these lines. 4

In any case, the objection can in fact be made with examples involving utterances which would be true by RTD. Consider the many-table scenario again. Suppose someone in that situation uttered (3) It s not the case that the table is covered with books. 3 I take it Russellians would assume, or regard as quite legitimate, that the domain of quantification includes the furniture in the room. In that case, the utterance should be heard as true, since the Russellian paraphrase: (3a) It s not the case that there is exactly one table and that whatever is a table is covered with books. is manifestly true with respect to that domain of quantification. But, intuitively, the utterance of (3) would be just as impenetrable as t. So, we can argue as follows. An utterance of (3) in the envisaged scenario would not appear inappropriate (improper) if the Russellian account were correct, whereas our intuition is that it most certainly would do. (Hence,... etc.) What moral should we draw from these clashes between RTD and our linguistic intuitions? The problematic utterances of (1) and (3) have the following feature in common: the utterer (in each case) evidently has no intention of referring, that is, of saying something about a particular object. I suggest it is precisely because of this absence of referential-intent that the user (or use) is regarded as deviant or the utterance as unintelligible. If my diagnosis is right, the moral of our considerations would appear to be that definite descriptions really are devices for referring to objects rather than quantifying over them; Russell s 3 I consider (3) instead of: The table is not covered with books precisely so as to preclude the primary-occurrence reading of the the table (see [4], p. 53). 5

quantificational treatment of them, however it is embellished, is, in that case, fundamentally mistaken. 4 References [1] Stephen Neale, Descriptions (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990) [2] Bertrand Russell, On Denoting, Mind, 14 (1905) 479-93. Also in Logic and Knowledge, edited by R. C. Marsh (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1956), 41-56, to which references apply. [3] P. F. Strawson, On Referring, Mind, 59 (1950) 320-44. Also in his Logico-Linguistic Papers (London: Methuen, 1971), 1-27, to which references apply. [4] P. F. Strawson, Introduction to Logical Theory (London: Methuen, 1952). 4 The main argument was presented to seminars at the Universities of Leeds and Cambridge. I thank the participants of those meetings for fruitful discussions. I also thank Graham Bird, Martin Davies, Jonardon Ganeri, Paul Noordhof and a referee for this journal for their comments on earlier drafts. 6