Agreement Between Scylla and Charybdis

Similar documents
Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

On the Notion Determiner

Chapter 4: Valence & Agreement CSLI Publications

An Interactive Intelligent Language Tutor Over The Internet

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

Control and Boundedness

The building blocks of HPSG grammars. Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG) HPSG grammars from a linguistic perspective

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

ENGBG1 ENGBL1 Campus Linguistics. Meeting 2. Chapter 7 (Morphology) and chapter 9 (Syntax) Pia Sundqvist

Hindi Aspectual Verb Complexes

Some Principles of Automated Natural Language Information Extraction

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

Theoretical Syntax Winter Answers to practice problems

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

Syntax Parsing 1. Grammars and parsing 2. Top-down and bottom-up parsing 3. Chart parsers 4. Bottom-up chart parsing 5. The Earley Algorithm

Structure-Preserving Extraction without Traces

Derivational: Inflectional: In a fit of rage the soldiers attacked them both that week, but lost the fight.

Gender and defaults *

BULATS A2 WORDLIST 2

Phenomena of gender attraction in Polish *

THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & SOCIAL STUDIES

Feature-Based Grammar

An Approach to Polarity Sensitivity and Negative Concord by Lexical Underspecification

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

Unit 8 Pronoun References

Compositional Semantics

Informatics 2A: Language Complexity and the. Inf2A: Chomsky Hierarchy

Tibor Kiss Reconstituting Grammar: Hagit Borer's Exoskeletal Syntax 1

Inleiding Taalkunde. Docent: Paola Monachesi. Blok 4, 2001/ Syntax 2. 2 Phrases and constituent structure 2. 3 A minigrammar of Italian 3

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

Argument structure and theta roles

Segmented Discourse Representation Theory. Dynamic Semantics with Discourse Structure

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

Construction Grammar. Laura A. Michaelis.

LFG Semantics via Constraints

Pre-Processing MRSes

SOME MINIMAL NOTES ON MINIMALISM *

Pseudo-Passives as Adjectival Passives

Derivational and Inflectional Morphemes in Pak-Pak Language

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

Heads and history NIGEL VINCENT & KERSTI BÖRJARS The University of Manchester

Using a Native Language Reference Grammar as a Language Learning Tool

Parsing of part-of-speech tagged Assamese Texts

Dependency, licensing and the nature of grammatical relations *

Chapter 3: Semi-lexical categories. nor truly functional. As Corver and van Riemsdijk rightly point out, There is more

Guidelines for Writing an Internship Report

The Structure of Multiple Complements to V

Words come in categories

Possessive have and (have) got in New Zealand English Heidi Quinn, University of Canterbury, New Zealand

Type Theory and Universal Grammar

THE SHORT ANSWER: IMPLICATIONS FOR DIRECT COMPOSITIONALITY (AND VICE VERSA) Pauline Jacobson. Brown University

Writing a composition

Specifying Logic Programs in Controlled Natural Language

ELA/ELD Standards Correlation Matrix for ELD Materials Grade 1 Reading

Advanced Grammar in Use

The Acquisition of English Grammatical Morphemes: A Case of Iranian EFL Learners

Annotating (Anaphoric) Ambiguity 1 INTRODUCTION. Paper presentend at Corpus Linguistics 2005, University of Birmingham, England

AQUA: An Ontology-Driven Question Answering System

Agree or Move? On Partial Control Anna Snarska, Adam Mickiewicz University

EAGLE: an Error-Annotated Corpus of Beginning Learner German

Language acquisition: acquiring some aspects of syntax.

Interfacing Phonology with LFG

Morphosyntactic and Referential Cues to the Identification of Generic Statements

1/20 idea. We ll spend an extra hour on 1/21. based on assigned readings. so you ll be ready to discuss them in class

Type-driven semantic interpretation and feature dependencies in R-LFG

Language Acquisition by Identical vs. Fraternal SLI Twins * Karin Stromswold & Jay I. Rifkin

Language Acquisition Fall 2010/Winter Lexical Categories. Afra Alishahi, Heiner Drenhaus

Developing Grammar in Context

LQVSumm: A Corpus of Linguistic Quality Violations in Multi-Document Summarization

Derivations (MP) and Evaluations (OT) *

Grammars & Parsing, Part 1:

Switched Control and other 'uncontrolled' cases of obligatory control

Word Formation is Syntactic: Raising in Nominalizations

The Structure of Relative Clauses in Maay Maay By Elly Zimmer

The Strong Minimalist Thesis and Bounded Optimality

Dear Teacher: Welcome to Reading Rods! Reading Rods offer many outstanding features! Read on to discover how to put Reading Rods to work today!

Campus Academic Resource Program An Object of a Preposition: A Prepositional Phrase: noun adjective

Construction Grammar. University of Jena.

What the National Curriculum requires in reading at Y5 and Y6

The presence of interpretable but ungrammatical sentences corresponds to mismatches between interpretive and productive parsing.

Som and Optimality Theory

Citation for published version (APA): Veenstra, M. J. A. (1998). Formalizing the minimalist program Groningen: s.n.

Intensive English Program Southwest College

Lecture 9. The Semantic Typology of Indefinites

Indeterminacy by Underspecification Mary Dalrymple (Oxford), Tracy Holloway King (PARC) and Louisa Sadler (Essex) (9) was: ( case) = nom ( case) = acc

ON THE SYNTAX AND SEMANTICS

Phonological and Phonetic Representations: The Case of Neutralization

Target Language Preposition Selection an Experiment with Transformation-Based Learning and Aligned Bilingual Data

Linguistic Variation across Sports Category of Press Reportage from British Newspapers: a Diachronic Multidimensional Analysis

BASIC ENGLISH. Book GRAMMAR

Modeling full form lexica for Arabic

The Effect of Extensive Reading on Developing the Grammatical. Accuracy of the EFL Freshmen at Al Al-Bayt University

Transcription:

Agreement Between Scylla and Charybdis Elizabeth Coppock October 16, 2012 Although Steve, Ivan and I never played in Dead Tongues (n.b.: no definite article) at the same time, we are all Dead Tongues at some level of representation, so it feels somehow natural that I sing the first verse of this tune before Steve takes it away with his solo, while Ivan provides the underlying harmonic structure for it all. In this short introduction, I will briefly summarize the HPSG theory of agreement and its motivations, and try to explain why it is brilliant. This should not replace reading the HPSG book (Pollard and Sag, 1994), which is more of an orchestral masterpiece. If you haven t read it, I highly recommend it, regardless of where you stand on the existence of empty categories. (It was one of the main reasons I wanted to go to Stanford for graduate school.) The distinctive and powerful thing about the HPSG theory of agreement is that it ties agreement together with reference, hence, with semantics. The theory centers around the notion of an index, which can be thought of either as a discourse referent in Discourse Representation Theory or as a parameter ( free variable) in situation semantics (Barwise and Perry, 1983). The idea is that the agreement features person, number and gender are features of indices, rather than of syntactic phrases, as was traditionally thought. The indices in question here are the same ones that play a central role in HPSG s non-configurational binding theory, its approach to subcategorization, and its storage-based approach to quantifier scope ambiguity, so the notion of index is importantly tied to multiple aspects of interpretation (and grammar). Making agreement features properties of indices thus results in a tight link between agreement and semantics. This connection has a number of useful empirical consequences. A purely syntactic theory of agreement would have trouble with the following contrast, illustrating the phenomenon of reference transfer: (1) a. The hash browns at table nine are/*is getting cold. b. The hash browns at table nine is/*are getting angry. Singular plurals, which will be discussed in Wechsler s paper, constitute another case that is tough for a purely syntactic theory of agreement: (2) Eggs is my favorite breakfast. (3) Doing phonology problems and drinking vodka makes me sick. 1

The singular/plural ambiguity of collectives, especially in British English, illustrates another problem for a purely syntactic theory of agreement: (4) The faculty are all agreed on this point. These facts can be accounted for by connecting the agreement features to the semantic index of the noun phrase. While avoiding the Scylla of a purely syntactic theory of agreement, however, this theory steers clear of the Charybdis of a purely semantic theory. This makes it possible to account for data that does not seem compatible with either extreme. (5) a. The faculty is voting itself a raise. b. The faculty are voting themselves a raise. c. *The faculty is voting themselves a raise. d. *The faculty are voting itself a raise. (6) a. That dog is so ferocious, it even tried to bite itself. b. That dog is so ferocious, he even tried to bite himself. c. *That dog is so ferocious, it even tried to bite himself. d. *That dog is so ferocious, he even tried to bit itself. (7) a. The ship lurched, and then it righted itself. b. The ship lurched, and then she righted herself. c. *The ship lurched, and then it righted herself. d. *The ship lurched, and then she righted itself. If agreement were purely semantic, then all four variants of these examples should be acceptable. The partly syntactic theory in HPSG accounts for these restrictions, by mediating the agreement relation through indices and requiring that pronouns and their antecedents share an index. Polite pronouns such as German Sie and French vous evince another advantage of the HPSG theory over a purely semantic theory. These involve a mismatch between semantic number and grammatical number: (8) Vous êtes l amour de ma vie. you.formal be.pres.2pl the:love of my life. You (formal) are the love of my life. If agreement were purely semantic, then it should not be possible for a plural verb to agree with a semantically singular subject. 1 1 However, as discussed by Pollard and Sag (1994, p. 96) polite pronouns participate in a phenomenon that remained somewhat puzzling under this view, namely mixed agreement, exemplified in Vous êtes belle you.formal be.pres.2plpretty.sg. In this case, the verb displays plural agreement and the adjective displays singular agreement. Evidently, predicative adjectives in French do not reflect the index number feature of the subject but rather the fact that the subject is semantically singular. It is in this connection that Wechsler and Zlatić (2003); Wechsler (2011) made an important contribution using two distinct feature bundles, index and concord. 2

Let s consider how the theory captures this data. In HPSG, unlike in many other theories, pronouns and common nouns have the same semantic type. The semantic value of both is essentially a pair consisting of an index and a restriction on that index. The elements of the pair have labels and are standardly represented in AVM format as in (9a), where the semantics of a commoun noun like pancake is shown. The boxed number indicates structure-sharing, which entails token-identity. Removing the labels gives us the pair in (9b), where u is the object that serves as the value of both the index feature and the inst feature. (9) a. per 3rd index 1 num sg gend neut [ reln pancake restr inst 1 b. u, {pancake(u)} The semantics of a pronoun is also a pair like this, except that the value of the restr feature is the empty set; in pair format, the semantics of a pronoun like she is u, {}. The requirement that u is female is stated among the constraints on the context. Proper names also have this type, and come with a contextual constraint that u bears the relevant name. What is the ontological status of the index u? Pollard and Sag tell us that we have at least two options: We can think of it either as a discourse referent or as a parameter in situation semantics. (Given that DRT can be embedded in situation semantics, maybe the latter is more specific than the former.) On the latter view, which is the one developed in more detail in Pollard and Sag (1994), the second member of the pair is a set of parameterized state of affairs (PSOA) as in situation semantics. If we think of u as a discourse referent, then the second element of the pair should be thought of as the bottom half of a Discourse Representation Structure (DRS) as in Discourse Representation Theory (Kamp and Reyle, 1993), which is a set of conditions. So the semantics of a common noun can be seen as a pair consisting of a discourse referent and a set of DRS-conditions. (It s almost like a DRS; if the first element of the pair were a set of discourse referents, then it would be.) 2 The representation in (9a) says a bit more about the index u than the representation in (9b) though. (9a) also tells us that u is 3rd person, singular, and neuter. These features are not mereological parts of the index, of course; they are properties of the index. So another way of thinking about this is that there 2 Note that if indices are discourse referents, then the semantic value of a word like pancake is a pair of terms in a representation language that must then be interpreted with respect to a model and an assignment function. For example if g is an assignment function and M is a model and g(u) = a, then it would be natural to assume that [u M,g = a. Semantic values in HPSG thus contain what might be referred to as representational objects, i.e., objects that represent the world rather than actual entities in a model. 3

is some function, call it π, whose domain is the set of indices and whose range is the set of possible person values (e.g. 1st, 2nd, and 3rd), and π(u) =3rd. Thus the HPSG theory of agreement is a general idea that can be implemented in any framework that has a notion of index and a function that assigns agreement features to indices. 3 Subject-verb agreement comes about through constraints imposed by inflected verb forms requiring token-identity of indices (hence, of person, number and gender features). A verb like succeed will have as its semantic content something which can be thought of either as a PSOA or a DRS-condition, e.g. succeed(u). The index u must also be the index of the subject. This identity requirement relates to the syntactic information associated with the verb (stored under the cat features) as illustrated in (10). (10) head verb[fin [ head noun cat cat subcat subcat loc [ pers 3rd cont index 1 num sg [ reln succeed cont inst 1 The semantic value of the verb is the value of its cont[ent feature, and this is a PSOA or DRS-condition which can be rewritten without labels as succeed(u). The index u serving as the argument of the succeed relation must be token-identical to the index of the subject, the first argument of the verb s subcat[egorization list. This theory of agreement can be contrasted with the one in for example Kamp and Reyle (1993), which is purely syntactic, despite the availability of discourse referents as part of the theory. There we have involving rules like the following, where α is a variable over different possible feature values (p. 30): (11) S Num=α NP Num=α VP Num=α Notice that number is treated as a feature of a syntactic phrase in this framework. Plural nouns are lexically specified as plural via rules like the following: (12) N Num=pl books, hash browns,... This set-up entails that the reference transfer-type cases will be ruled out as ungrammatical. By treating agreement features as features of indices, which 3 One would have to be careful when undertaking such an enterprise, as HPSG indices can be non-referential; the English expletives it and there have non-referential indices and it is not clear whether they introduce discourse referents. 4

are tied to semantics, the HPSG theory of agreement gets the leeway it needs to deal with reference transfer, singular plurals, and collectives. Like subject-verb agreement, pronoun-antecedent agreement also relies on indices according to the HPSG binding theory. A reflexive pronoun, for example, must share an index with its antecedent. This explains why the (c) and (d) examples in (5)-(7), in which there is a mismatch between a reflexive pronoun and its antecedent, are unacceptable. A purely semantic theory would allow these kinds of mismatches, since it would allow any pronoun whose features correspond to some possible conceptualization of the referent. In contrast, agreement features are still part of the grammar under the HPSG theory, even though they are connected to semantics. In this way, the HPSG theory nagivates the tricky passage between Scylla and Charybdis. I would like to underline the point that the HPSG theory of agreement is a general idea that can be implemented in any framework that has a notion of index, as one has in every framework that makes use of discourse referents. The sign-based nature of HPSG makes it particularly suited for an implementation of this type of theory, as constraints crossing the border between form and content can easily be stated as contraints on signs. But all one really needs beyond a notion of index is a function that assigns agreement features to indices, and a way to relate these functions to verb forms. Even if you don t do HPSG, if you have these things, then you too can make all of these lovely predictions. Take it away, Steve. References Barwise, J. and Perry, J. (1983). Situations and Attitudes. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Kamp, H. and Reyle, U. (1993). From Discourse to Logic. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht. Pollard, C. and Sag, I. A. (1994). Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Wechsler, S. (2011). Mixed agreement, the person feature, and the Index/Concord distinction. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 29(4):999 1031. Wechsler, S. and Zlatić, L. (2003). The Many Faces of Agreement: Morphology, Syntax, Semantics, and Discourse Factors in Serbo-Croatian Agreement. CSLI Publications, Stanford. 5