On the status of Maximize Presupposition

Similar documents
Specification and Evaluation of Machine Translation Toy Systems - Criteria for laboratory assignments

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Focusing bound pronouns

The Bulgarian Reportative as a Conventional Implicature Chronos 10. Dimka Atanassov University of Pennsylvania

The presence of interpretable but ungrammatical sentences corresponds to mismatches between interpretive and productive parsing.

Does Linguistic Communication Rest on Inference?

Control and Boundedness

An Introduction to the Minimalist Program

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF MINNESOTA BY. Kaitlin Rose Johnson

Replies to Greco and Turner

Parallel Evaluation in Stratal OT * Adam Baker University of Arizona

Segmented Discourse Representation Theory. Dynamic Semantics with Discourse Structure

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

A New Semantics for Number

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

Relevance Theory and the saying/implicating distinction *

An Interactive Intelligent Language Tutor Over The Internet

PROCESS USE CASES: USE CASES IDENTIFICATION

Abstractions and the Brain

An Approach to Polarity Sensitivity and Negative Concord by Lexical Underspecification

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Declarative Questions

1. Programme title and designation International Management N/A

Common Core State Standards for English Language Arts

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

Derivations (MP) and Evaluations (OT) *

MEASURING ORDINARY MEANING USING SURVEYS JP SEVILLA 3L and Levy Fellow George Mason University School of Law September 10, 2014

Som and Optimality Theory

Transitive meanings for intransitive verbs

Tutoring First-Year Writing Students at UNM

5 Minimalism and Optimality Theory

Visual CP Representation of Knowledge

Gricean Communication and Transmission of Thoughts

AN INTRODUCTION (2 ND ED.) (LONDON, BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC PP. VI, 282)

Rubric for Scoring English 1 Unit 1, Rhetorical Analysis

ESC Declaration and Management of Conflict of Interest Policy

The Strong Minimalist Thesis and Bounded Optimality

BUILD-IT: Intuitive plant layout mediated by natural interaction

Entrepreneurial Discovery and the Demmert/Klein Experiment: Additional Evidence from Germany

PHILOSOPHY & CULTURE Syllabus

Degree Comparisons across Possible Worlds: Measure Phrase Modification with -(i)na *

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

Some Principles of Automated Natural Language Information Extraction

Monsters and the theoretical role of context

COMPUTATIONAL COMPLEXITY OF LEFT-ASSOCIATIVE GRAMMAR

MA Linguistics Language and Communication

A cautionary note is research still caught up in an implementer approach to the teacher?

Parsing of part-of-speech tagged Assamese Texts

To appear in The TESOL encyclopedia of ELT (Wiley-Blackwell) 1 RECASTING. Kazuya Saito. Birkbeck, University of London

Myers-Briggs Type Indicator Team Report

THE SHORT ANSWER: IMPLICATIONS FOR DIRECT COMPOSITIONALITY (AND VICE VERSA) Pauline Jacobson. Brown University

Context-Sensitive Bidirectional OT: a New Approach to Russian Aspect

How to analyze visual narratives: A tutorial in Visual Narrative Grammar

b) Allegation means information in any form forwarded to a Dean relating to possible Misconduct in Scholarly Activity.

CEFR Overall Illustrative English Proficiency Scales

A is an inde nite nominal pro-form that takes antecedents. ere have

The Verbmobil Semantic Database. Humboldt{Univ. zu Berlin. Computerlinguistik. Abstract

Information Structure and Referential Givenness/Newness: How Much Belongs in the Grammar?

THEORY OF PLANNED BEHAVIOR MODEL IN ELECTRONIC LEARNING: A PILOT STUDY

Possessive have and (have) got in New Zealand English Heidi Quinn, University of Canterbury, New Zealand

Adjectival Extremeness: Degree Modification and Contextually Restricted Scales

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

MASN: 1 How would you define pragmatics today? How is it different from traditional Greek rhetorics? What are its basic tenets?

English Policy Statement and Syllabus Fall 2017 MW 10:00 12:00 TT 12:15 1:00 F 9:00 11:00

The Discourse Effects of the Indefinite Demonstrative dieser in German

Types and Lexical Semantics

An Empirical Analysis of the Effects of Mexican American Studies Participation on Student Achievement within Tucson Unified School District

In Reich, Ingo et al. (eds.), Proceedings of Sinn & Bedeutung 15, pp Universaar Saarland University Press: Saarbrücken, Germany, 2011.

How do adults reason about their opponent? Typologies of players in a turn-taking game

DEPARTMENT OF MOLECULAR AND CELL BIOLOGY

The Effect of Discourse Markers on the Speaking Production of EFL Students. Iman Moradimanesh

Utilizing Soft System Methodology to Increase Productivity of Shell Fabrication Sushant Sudheer Takekar 1 Dr. D.N. Raut 2

TEACHING AND EXAMINATION REGULATIONS PART B: programme-specific section MASTER S PROGRAMME IN LOGIC

U : Second Semester French

A. What is research? B. Types of research

The role of the first language in foreign language learning. Paul Nation. The role of the first language in foreign language learning

Procedural pragmatics and the study of discourse Louis de Saussure

Interpreting Vague Utterances in Context

Intension, Attitude, and Tense Annotation in a High-Fidelity Semantic Representation

Motivation to e-learn within organizational settings: What is it and how could it be measured?

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

CONTENUTI DEL CORSO (presentazione di disciplina, argomenti, programma):

Going back to our roots: disciplinary approaches to pedagogy and pedagogic research

Higher education is becoming a major driver of economic competitiveness

(Re)Formalizing the Imperative Sentence Type. David Medeiros,

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

Constraints on metalinguistic anaphora

EFFECTIVE CLASSROOM MANAGEMENT UNDER COMPETENCE BASED EDUCATION SCHEME

On Labeling: Principle C and Head Movement

STUDENT ASSESSMENT AND EVALUATION POLICY

Classroom Connections Examining the Intersection of the Standards for Mathematical Content and the Standards for Mathematical Practice

L1 and L2 acquisition. Holger Diessel

Causal Link Semantics for Narrative Planning Using Numeric Fluents

University of Groningen. Systemen, planning, netwerken Bosman, Aart

Strategic discourse comprehension

Master s Thesis. An Agent-Based Platform for Dialogue Management

Formative Assessment in Mathematics. Part 3: The Learner s Role

Transcription:

On the status of Maximize Presupposition Sven Lauer (sven@sven-lauer.net) Georg-August-University Göttingen Abstract Heim (1991) postulated the principle Maximize Presupposition (MP), which has proven useful in explanations of a range of phenomena that involve competition between two forms that differ in their semantic presuppositions. But what kind of principle is MP? Is it a normative constraint on language use, akin to a rule in a game? Or is it similar, as Heim s original postulation suggests, to Grice (1975) s Maxims of Conversation, which capture defeasible tendencies in behavior motivated by general considerations about cooperative communication? The first view is favored by the observation that obvious violations of MP lead to infelicity, the second is favored by the observation that there are cases where MP appears to be obviated. This talk resolves this tension and argues that inferences triggered by MP can in fact be analyzed as Gricean pragmatic inferences, provided MP is construed as a linguistic preference a (selfish) preference between linguistic expressions that speakers happen to have. In this view, MP is neither a normative rule nor a maxim motivated by general considerations of cooperative behaviour, but it functions like, and interacts with, such maxims in pragmatic reasoning. 1

Heim (1991) postulated the principle Maximize Presupposition (MP), which has proven useful in explanations of a range of phenomena that involve competition between two forms that differ in their semantic presuppositions (Sauerland 2008, Percus 2006, Chemla 2008, Singh 2011, Leahy 2011, a.o.). On an informal level, MP requires speakers to presuppose as much as possible i.e. to opt for an expression with stronger (semantic) presuppositions if these presuppositions are (known to be) satisfied in context. But what kind of principle is MP? Is it a normative constraint on language use, akin to a rule in a game? Or is it similar, as Heim s original postulation suggests, to Grice s (1975) Maxims of Conversation, which capture defeasible tendencies in behavior motivated by general considerations about cooperative communication? Two basic observations create a tension between these two options: Infelicities. One of the reasons Heim originally postulated MP was to help explain infelicities like the following. (1) a. #A sun is shining. does not presuppose: There is at most one sun. b. The sun is shining presupposes: There is at most one sun. (1a) is supposedly infelicitous because, in normal contexts, it will always be common ground that there is exactly one sun. Consequently, the speaker of (1a) fails to obey MP. If MP is a normative principle of language use, then it stands to reason that violating it directly leads to infelicity. But if MP instead is more like a Gricean maxim, it is not obvious why infelicity should result from a violation of the principle. Obvious violations of Gricean maxims may make the speaker appear uncooperative, but it is not clear why they should lead to the utterance to be deemed deviant. Obviations. On the other hand, there are clear cases where MP appears to be obviated that is, cases where a speaker can felicitously use a non-presupposing form rather than its presupposing alternative, even though it is part of the common ground that the additional presupposition of the alternative is true. (2) is an example. (2) [Context: The constitution of Phantasia stipulates: A son of the king has to be present at the opening of the parliament. It is known to everyone that the current king has exactly one son, who is in attendance. Running through the regulations during the opening ceremony, the speaker of parliament declares:] As the constitution demands, all MPs have pledged their allegiance to the king, a son of the king is present,... Intuitively, what makes (2) okay, despite the apparent violation of MP, is that the speaker s use of the indefinite parallels the statement of the rules. If MP is a normative constraint on language use, which is strong enough to explain infelicities like (1a), then it is difficult to see how such obviations can be accommodated (except by adding ad hoc exception clauses to the formulation of the principle). But if MP instead is more like a Gricean maxim, then it stands to reason that it interacts with other pragmatic concerns, and hence can be obviated in certain contexts. 2

Non-Gricean features of previous accounts When MP does not trigger infelicities (and is not obviated), it gives rise implicature-like inferences so-called anti-presuppositions to the effect that the presupposition of the stronger alternative is not true (or, minimally, that the speaker is not certain that the presupposition is true, Chemla 2008), as in (3). (3) a. Mary knows that Bill has a new boyfriend. presupposes: Bill has a new boyfriend. b. Mary believes that Bill has a new boyfriend. does not presuppose: Bill has a new boyfriend. hence (?) implicates: Speaker is not certain that Bill has a new boyfriend. hence may implicate: Bill does not have a new boyfriend. On a Gricean conception, this makes it tempting to assume that what makes (1a) odd is not the obvious violation of MP per se, but rather the fact that the speaker implicates something that is mutually known to be false. This tack sets up a new tension, however, as Gricean implicatures are generally taken to be optional, and hence expected to be absent when they are incompatible with the context. In addition, recent formulations and applications of the principle have introduced more non-gricean features. Percus (2006) formulated MP as in (4), using the notions of lexical alternatives and Alternative-Family as in (5). His formulation not only suggests an understanding of MP as a normative rule, but also (indirectly, through the definition of lexical alternatives) makes the principle sensitive to lexical presuppositions. As Singh (2011) points out, it is quite unclear why a general principle of cooperative behavior should make reference to lexical properties of expressions. (4) MP-prohibition (Percus 2006) Do not use φ if a member of its Alternative-Family ψ is felicitous and contextually equivalent toφ. (5) a. Lexical Alternatives: Lexical items i are associated with a set of lexical alternatives that are presuppositionally stronger thani. b. Alternative-Family: The Alternative-Family of a sentence φ is the set of sentences obtained by replacing a lexical item inφwith one of its lexical alternatives. In part to avoid this reference to lexical presuppositions, Schlenker (2012) and Singh (2011) proposed that MP is checked not (or not only) globally for the whole utterance, but that it must be satisfied in embedded positions ( local contexts ). This is squarely at odds with the general conception of Gricean reasoning as a global process that is blind to the grammatical structure of the utterance. Of course, there has been a lively debate recently that certain implicatures arise in embedded positions, but it is largely agreed that, if these inferences truly arise in embedded positions, then they cannot be considered Gricean implicatures. Defenders of Gricean accounts of these inferences have hence sought to show that they only appear to arise in embedded positions. Consequently, if MP indeed has to be checked in embedded positions, this makes it necessary to consider the principle a bona fide grammatical constraint, rather than a Gricean principle of conversation. 3

MP as a linguistic preference I argue that we can maintain that the effects of MP arise in a truly Gricean manner as global, pragmatic implications of utterances driven by general reasoning about how (boundedly) rational agents behave in cooperative settings. In order to do so, we need to construe the principle neither as a normative rule, nor as a maxim that arises from general considerations of cooperative behavior. Instead, we need to conceive of it is a preference between linguistic forms that speakers happen to have (and that addressees know they have) a linguistic preference. I advocate a return to Percus formulation in terms of lexical alternatives. As such, the principle is not really a principle that enjoins the speaker to prefer sentences with certain contents. Rather, it is a principle that enjoins speakers to prefer certain lexical items over others (where the items in question happen to be identified by reference to a semantic feature of the lexical entries viz. their lexical presuppositions). To make its nature as a speaker preference (rather than a normative rule) transparent, I propose to recast Percus formulation as follows: (6) MP-preference Other things being equal, the members ofφ s Alternative-Family are preferred toφ. MP-preference generates Need A Reason implicatures Even though it is not a normative constraint, a preference like (6) can be used to explain infelicities like (1a). As Lauer (2013) shows, ceteris paribus preferences between forms generate robust Gricean inferences that will lead to infelicity if they are known to be false. In a nutshell, given a context-independent preference that favors one formψover anotherφ, on any occasion whereφis uttered, the speaker must have a reason to refrain from uttering the otherwise-preferred ψ. Crucially, if no such reason can be inferred or accommodated,φwill be infelicitous, as the addressee cannot make sense of the speaker s utterance choice. This will frequently happen if the presupposition of the stronger alternative is commonly known to be true (which, of course, is particularly likely if the presupposition is part of entrenched world knowledge, as in (1)) for in that case, the speaker cannot have an information-related reason. It cannot be that he avoided the stronger alternative because he did not know, or did not want to reveal, that the presupposition is satisfied. This kind of account is crucially different from one that construes MP as a normative principle of behavior, in that it effortlessly deals with obviations as in (2) while there cannot be an information-related reason in this case (as the presupposition that the king has a unique son is common knowledge), there is a non-information-based reason why the speaker did not use the otherwise-preferred form (viz. a preference for parallelism with the text of the law). Conclusion. The existence of obviations of Maximize Presupposition strongly suggests an understanding of the inferences triggered by the principle in Gricean terms. This talk argues that such an understanding is feasible, but only if we (a) return to a Percusian formulation of MP in terms of lexical presuppositions and (b) reconstrue it as a ceteris paribus preference between forms. Once we do, antipresuppositions turn out to be a species of the Need a Reason implicatures of Lauer (2013), which, as Lauer shows, are predicted by the majority of current formal accounts of Gricean reasoning. 4

References Chemla, E.: 2008, An epistemic step for anti-presuppositions, Journal of Semantics 25, 141 173. Grice, H. P.: 1975, Logic and conversation, in P. Cole and J. L. Morgan (eds), Speech Acts, Vol. 3 of Syntax and Semantics, Academic Press, pp. 41 58. Heim, I.: 1991, Artikel und Definitheit [Articles and definiteness], in A. von Stechow and D. Wunderlich (eds), Semantik: Ein internationales Handbuch der zeitgenössischen Forschung, de Gruyter, Berlin, pp. 487 535. Lauer, S.: 2013, Towards a dynamic pragmatics, PhD thesis, Stanford University. Leahy, B.: 2011, Presuppositions and antipresuppositions in conditionals, in N. Ashton, A. Chereches and D. Lutz (eds), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 21, pp. 257 274. Percus, O.: 2006, Antipresuppositions, in A. Ueyama (ed.), Theoretical and Empirical Studies of Reference and Anaphora: Toward the establishment of generative grammar as an empiral science. [Report of the Grant-in-Aid for Scientific Research (B)], Japan Society for the Promotion of Science, pp. 52 73. Sauerland, U.: 2008, Implicated presuppositions, in A. Steube (ed.), Sentences and context: Language, context, and cognition, De Gruyter. Schlenker, P.: 2012, Maximize presuposition and Gricean reasoning, Natural Language Semantics 20, 391 429. Singh, R.: 2011, Maximize Presupposition! and local contexts, Natural Language Semantics 19, 149 168. 5