continues to assume a separation between positions where elements are generated (the

Similar documents
VERB MOVEMENT The Status of the Weak Pronouns in Dutch

Argument structure and theta roles

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

Citation for published version (APA): Veenstra, M. J. A. (1998). Formalizing the minimalist program Groningen: s.n.

Agree or Move? On Partial Control Anna Snarska, Adam Mickiewicz University

SOME MINIMAL NOTES ON MINIMALISM *

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

Pseudo-Passives as Adjectival Passives

Som and Optimality Theory

Korean ECM Constructions and Cyclic Linearization

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

Theoretical Syntax Winter Answers to practice problems

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

An Introduction to the Minimalist Program

Control and Boundedness

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

The presence of interpretable but ungrammatical sentences corresponds to mismatches between interpretive and productive parsing.

Words come in categories

Hindi-Urdu Phrase Structure Annotation

A comment on the topic of topic comment

Writing a composition

THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & SOCIAL STUDIES

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

Advanced Grammar in Use

Developing Grammar in Context

The Structure of Relative Clauses in Maay Maay By Elly Zimmer

Derivational and Inflectional Morphemes in Pak-Pak Language

LIN 6520 Syntax 2 T 5-6, Th 6 CBD 234

The Inclusiveness Condition in Survive-minimalism

Chapter 3: Semi-lexical categories. nor truly functional. As Corver and van Riemsdijk rightly point out, There is more

The Lexical Representation of Light Verb Constructions

In Udmurt (Uralic, Russia) possessors bear genitive case except in accusative DPs where they receive ablative case.

German Superiority *

Today we examine the distribution of infinitival clauses, which can be

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

When a Complement PP Goes Missing: A Study on the Licensing Condition of Swiping

Derivations (MP) and Evaluations (OT) *

Update on Soar-based language processing

CHILDREN S POSSESSIVE STRUCTURES: A CASE STUDY 1. Andrew Radford and Joseph Galasso, University of Essex

Construction Grammar. University of Jena.

On the Notion Determiner

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Long-distance wh-movement. Long distance wh-movement. Islands. Islands. Locality. NP Sea. NP Sea

On Labeling: Principle C and Head Movement

Intervention in Tough Constructions * Jeremy Hartman. Massachusetts Institute of Technology

Inleiding Taalkunde. Docent: Paola Monachesi. Blok 4, 2001/ Syntax 2. 2 Phrases and constituent structure 2. 3 A minigrammar of Italian 3

Linguistic Variation across Sports Category of Press Reportage from British Newspapers: a Diachronic Multidimensional Analysis

The optimal placement of up and ab A comparison 1

IS THERE A PASSIVE IN DHOLUO?

1/20 idea. We ll spend an extra hour on 1/21. based on assigned readings. so you ll be ready to discuss them in class

Phenomena of gender attraction in Polish *

Loughton School s curriculum evening. 28 th February 2017

5 Minimalism and Optimality Theory

The semantics of case *

The subject of adjectives: Syntactic position and semantic interpretation

LEXICAL COHESION ANALYSIS OF THE ARTICLE WHAT IS A GOOD RESEARCH PROJECT? BY BRIAN PALTRIDGE A JOURNAL ARTICLE

a) analyse sentences, so you know what s going on and how to use that information to help you find the answer.

A Computational Evaluation of Case-Assignment Algorithms

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

GERM 3040 GERMAN GRAMMAR AND COMPOSITION SPRING 2017

Two$Asymmetries$between$Pre0$and$Post0Head$Order$ and$their$implications$for$syntactic$theory$

Parasitic participles and ellipsis in VP-focus pseudoclefts. Jan-Wouter Zwart

Presentation Exercise: Chapter 32

California Department of Education English Language Development Standards for Grade 8

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

MA Linguistics Language and Communication

Chapter 9 Banked gap-filling

Direct and Indirect Passives in East Asian. C.-T. James Huang Harvard University

Strategic Practice: Career Practitioner Case Study

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

Diagnostic Test. Middle School Mathematics

BULATS A2 WORDLIST 2

Two Ways of Expressing Negation. Hedde H. Zeijlstra

Rote rehearsal and spacing effects in the free recall of pure and mixed lists. By: Peter P.J.L. Verkoeijen and Peter F. Delaney

Heads and history NIGEL VINCENT & KERSTI BÖRJARS The University of Manchester

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Part I. Figuring out how English works

1 Nonapriorism vs. apriorism

Welcome to the Purdue OWL. Where do I begin? General Strategies. Personalizing Proofreading

An Empirical and Computational Test of Linguistic Relativity

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

Dependency, licensing and the nature of grammatical relations *

Context Free Grammars. Many slides from Michael Collins

Grammars & Parsing, Part 1:

Iraqi EFL Students' Achievement In The Present Tense And Present Passive Constructions

What the National Curriculum requires in reading at Y5 and Y6

Intensive English Program Southwest College

The Acquisition of Person and Number Morphology Within the Verbal Domain in Early Greek

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Tibor Kiss Reconstituting Grammar: Hagit Borer's Exoskeletal Syntax 1

CAAP. Content Analysis Report. Sample College. Institution Code: 9011 Institution Type: 4-Year Subgroup: none Test Date: Spring 2011

On the Head Movement of Complex Nominal Predicates * Andrew Carnie Massachusetts Institute of Technology

Unit 8 Pronoun References

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

Using dialogue context to improve parsing performance in dialogue systems

The Strong Minimalist Thesis and Bounded Optimality

UC Merced Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society

A GENERIC SPLIT PROCESS MODEL FOR ASSET MANAGEMENT DECISION-MAKING

Transcription:

Object Shift with Raising Verbs C. Jan-Wouter Zwart In recent minimalist work hypothesizing multiple specifiers to a single head (Chomsky 1995, section 4.10; Chomsky 1998) it is proposed that objects are formally licensed in an outer specifier of vp, a projection headed by a light verb representing causative or agentive semantics: (1) vp OB v EXT v v VP V INT In (1), the positions where the subject and direct object are generated are indicated (as EXT and INT, respectively), as well as the position where the object is formally licensed (OB). In comparison to earlier analyses in the Principles and Parameters framework, the proposal continues to assume a separation between positions where elements are generated (the theta-positions) and positions where elements are formally licensed (the Case positions), but the formal licensing positions are no longer defined as specifiers to separate functional agreement heads, as in (2):

(2) AgrOP OB AgrO AgrO vp EXT v v VP V INT The structure in (1) has the advantage that two seemingly independent relations, namely assignment of a theta role to the external argument and assignment of ( accusative ) Case to the direct object, are concentrated in a single head, v. That these two functions are related is expressed in the so-called Burzio Generalization (Burzio 1986:178): (3) Burzio s Generalization a. A verb which does not take an external argument does not assign accusative Case. b. A verb which does not assign accusative Case does not take an external argument. In earlier frameworks, the correlations expressed in (3) could not be fully explained. Assuming the structure in (1), (3) is explained if a verb which does not assign an external argument simply lacks vp in its verb phrase structure (cf. Chomsky 1995:316). In this squib, I present an argument showing that the reduction of a structure like (2) to a structure like (1) is nevertheless incorrect. The evidence involves restructuring constructions in Dutch, where the internal argument of an embedded verb is formally licensed in the functional domain of a matrix verb which itself does not take an external

argument. If verbs without external argument lack vp, the formal licensing position for the internal argument of the embedded verb cannot be the outer specifier of a vp, but must be a specifier of an independent functional head. This is accommodated in (2), but not in (1). 1 Consider first a simple perception verb construction in Dutch: (4)..dat ik Jan gisteren zag that I John yesterday see-past Here the argument of the perception verb zag saw, Jan, is separated from the verb by the sentence adverb gisteren yesterday. Following Vanden Wyngaerd (1989), I take this to imply that the object noun phrase moves to a licensing position in the functional domain. Vanden Wyngaerd, who shows by application of standard tests (locality and binding), that the object shift is A-movement, describes the object s licensing position as Spec,AgrOP (5a). 2 In the structure (1) proposed by Chomsky (1995), the licensing position would be the outer specifier position of v (5b): 3 (5) a... [ CP dat [ ik [ AgrOP Jan [ vp gisteren [ vp <ik> [ VP zag <Jan> ]]]]]] b... [ CP dat [ ik [ vp Jan [ v gisteren [ v <ik> [ VP zag <Jan> ]]]]]] In an Exceptional Case-marking construction involving the same perception verb, the external argument of the embedded verb appears in the same position in the functional domain of the matrix verb as is occupied by the internal argument of the perception verb

in (4): (6)..dat ik Jan gisteren zag winnen that I John yesterday saw win In a Principles and Parameters analysis (cf. (2)), this position would again be Spec,AgrOP (7a), whereas in Chomsky s (1995) proposal (cf. (1)), it would be the outer specifier of vp (7b): (7) a... [ CP dat [ AgrSP ik [ AgrOP Jan [ vp gisteren [ vp <ik> [ VP zag [ vp <Jan> [ VP winnen ]]]]]]]] b... [ CP dat [ TP ik [ vp Jan [ v gisteren [ v <ik> [ VP zag [ vp <Jan> [ VP winnen ]]]]]]]] If the embedded verb winnen win takes an internal argument such as de race the race, it, too, is moved to a licensing position in the functional domain of the matrix verb: (8)..dat ik Jan de race gisteren zag winnen that I John the race yesterday saw win For the agreement phrase analysis (2), this implies that a sequence of AgrOPs must be assumed (9a). For the multiple specifier analysis (1), it implies that the number of outer specifiers to v may be increased to accommodate the number of arguments to be licensed

(9b): (9) a... [ CP dat [ AgrSP ik [ AgrOP Jan [ AgrOP de race [ vp gisteren [ vp <ik> [ VP zag [ vp <Jan> [ VP winnen ]]]]]]]]] b... [ CP dat [ TP ik [ vp Jan [ v de race [ v gisteren [ v <ik> [ VP zag [ vp <Jan> [ VP winnen ]]]]]]]]] Neither assumption seems particularly problematic. 4 Notice that the perception verb zien itself is a transitive verb, which therefore implies the presence of vp in the matrix clause. The examples in (5) and (7) suggest a generalization along the lines in (10), which is often held to be true: (10) A verb. can appear as the matrix verb in an Exceptional Case-marking construction iff. is a transitive (accusative Case assigning) verb. These cases, then, do not help us decide whether object noun phrases are licensed in the specifier position of vp, as in (1), or in the specifier position of a separate functional head, as in (2). The following set of facts, however, does. Raising verbs in Dutch, like schijnen seem, show the same transparency effects as perception verbs. The only difference is that raising verbs, unlike perception verbs, take no external argument. If the embedded verb is transitive, its external argument raises to the subject position of the matrix clause, and the internal argument raises to the same object

licensing position that we saw in (4), (6), and (8): 5 (11)..dat Jan de race gisteren scheen te zullen winnen that John the race yesterday seemed to will win Schijnen seem, being a raising verb, has no external argument and does not by itself have the ability to assign accusative Case to a grammatical object: (12) a. * Piet schijnt Pete seems b. # Piet schijnt een idioot Pete seems an idiot (12b) is interpretable only as a (quasi) copular construction, not as a transitive construction. Since schijnen takes no external argument, we must conclude, by (3), that it has no vp in its verb phrase structure. This means that (11) can only be analyzed as in (13), with a structure involving a separate functional projection for licensing a grammatical object: (13).. [ CP dat [ AgrSP Jan [ AgrOP de race [ VP gisteren [ VP scheen [ TP te zullen [ vp <Jan> [ VP winnen <de race> ]]]]]]]] Sentences like (11), then, demonstrate that object licensing may take place in the absence

of a vp. This is accommodated by the structure in (2), but not by the structure in (1). (11) also shows the generalization in (10) to be incorrect. The correct generalization appears to be the following: (14) Formal licensing of an object in the functional domain of a verb. takes place (i) when. has an external argument, or (ii) when. is a restructuring verb, and the verb in the complement domain of. has an external argument If (14) is correct, the requirement on Exceptional Case-marking in (10) is too strong. If the Exceptional Case-marking verb is a restructuring verb, the only requirement is that the verb in its complement domain is a transitive verb. Many other examples may be construed which demonstrate the same point. (15) is an example of a transitive expletive construction (TEC), (16) of a passive construction: 6 (15)..dat er iemand het huis gisteren scheen te zullen kopen that there someone the house yesterday seemed to will buy.. that someone yesterday seemed to be going to buy the house (16)..dat Jan het boek niet werd geacht te hebben gelezen that John the book not was considered-part to have read-part that John was not considered to have read the book

(15) shows three phrases in the functional domain of the matrix clause (i.e. to the left of the matrix adverb gisteren yesterday ), which in the Principles and Parameters theory of clause structure may be taken to occupy the specifier positions of AgrSP, TP, and AgrOP (cf.chomsky 1995:342). The matrix verb is again schijnen, which lacks a vp. But schijnen is a restructuring verb, having a transitive verb, kopen buy, in its complement domain. Hence, the presence of a position for formal licensing of the object is due to the presence of a transitive verb in the complement domain of the matrix verb. (Chomsky s 1995, section 4.10 discussion of TECs ignores the crucial cases, where the TEC involves a multiverb construction with an unaccusative matrix verb.) (16) involves a passive matrix verb, a standard case covered by the Burzio Generalization (3). Thus, passive verbs do not express an external argument, and fail to assign accusative Case. In the current framework, this is most elegantly described if we assume that passive verbs lack vp. Again, the object het boek the book cannot be licensed in the specifier position of a vp. Crucially, however, there is a transitive verb lezen read in the complement domain of the matrix verb, and the construction as a whole is a restructuring construction. Again, all that seems to be required is transitivity somewhere in the restructuring complex, not necessarily in the matrix clause. The facts discussed provide a strikingly compelling argument in support of the structure in (2). In view of this, we need to consider potential weaknesses of the argumentation. The weakest spot appears to be the assumption that raising verbs lack vp. This assumption, though based on Burzio s Generalization (3), may be wrong, and if it is, the argument simply collapses. 7

However, it can be shown quite easily that assuming raising verbs to have a vp would be missing a number of significant generalizations. First, since v represents causative or agentive semantics (Chomsky 1995:315), and raising verbs lack a causer or agent to appear as an external argument to v, the claim that raising verbs involve vp is not semantically motivated. In other words, the decision to merge VP with v can only be made on the basis of look ahead, namely to provide a licensing position for an object in the relevant constructions. Second, even if raising verbs standardly involve a vp, the nominal feature of v that attracts an object noun phrase to its specifier position can only be active (or present) under very specific circumstances. These circumstances can be described entirely on the basis of the transitivity of the embedded verb. Thus, the v of the raising verb would be inactive when the embedded verb is unaccusative, passive, or unergative. In those cases, the single argument of the embedded verb is licensed as the subject of the matrix clause: (17)..dat Jan niet scheen te sterven / worden gearresteerd / dansen that John not seemed to die / be arrested / dance In those cases, the raising verb s v must not be active, or else the raised noun phrase would no longer be available for raising to the matrix subject position. The only situation, then, where the raising verb s v would be needed is when the embedded verb is transitive, as in (11), (15), and (16). Third, it can be shown that restructuring complexes as a whole are subject to Burzio s

Generalization. Thus, in raising constructions with a transitive embedded verb, like (11), where the internal argument of the embedded verb is licensed in the object position of the matrix clause, passivizing the embedded verb has the effect that the object position of the matrix clause is eliminated. Compare the sentences in (18): (18) a...dat Jan de race niet scheen te winnen that John the race not seemed to win b...dat de race (door Jan) niet scheen te worden gewonnen that the race by John not seemed to be won-part In (18a), a position for licensing the object of winnen win is needed in the matrix clause. But in (18b), where winnen is passivized, such a position is no longer needed. This is a standard effect of Burzio s Generalization (3), but now the absence of an external argument in the embedded clause precludes accusative Case assignment in the matrix clause. This indicates that the object licensing position in the matrix clause is a function of the presence of vp in the embedded clause. Assuming that the structure of raising verbs involves a vp misses this generalization entirely. I would like to propose that restructuring has the effect that the potential for licensing an object is passed on from the embedded verb (in fact, the v of the embedded verb) to the matrix verb. Burzio s Generalization then holds of the entire set of verbs in a restructuring complex. We might say that v launches an AgrOP, and that in restructuring contexts, the AgrOP is licensed in the functional domain of the matrix verb.

The facts discussed in this squib show that the relation between transitivity (the presence of vp in a verb phrase) and formal licensing of an object noun phrase (accusative Case assignment) is indirect. Consequently, the object cannot be licensed in the outer specifier of vp, but must be licensed in the specifier position of a functional projection that is dependent on, but structurally separated from vp. References Burzio, Luigi. 1986. Italian syntax: a Government-Binding approach. Dordrecht: Reidel. Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Chomsky, Noam. 1998. Minimalist inquiries: the framework. Ms., MIT, Cambridge, Mass. Vanden Wyngaerd, Guido. 1989. Object Shift as an A-movement rule. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 11, 256-271. Zwart, C. Jan-Wouter. 1994. Dutch is head initial. The Linguistic Review 11, 377-406.

Notes Thanks to Eric Hoekstra, Jan Koster, Ian Roberts, Cédric Boeckx, and the participants in the OTS/UiL graduate course Multiple Specifiers and Locality of A-Movement taught by the author in the Spring of 1999. The author s research is supported by a grant from the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO), file nr. 300-75-027, which is gratefully acknowledged. 1 In Dutch, restructuring verbs include perception verbs, causative verbs, raising verbs, and a limited number of control verbs. Restructuring has the effect that the lower verb s arguments are formally licensed in the functional domain of the higher verb (yielding raising to object or exceptional Case-marking). The exact conditions and operations giving rise to restructuring cannot be discussed in the context of this squib. 2 The argumentation in this squib is independent of the exact analysis of Dutch phrase structure (a head initial structure is assumed here, cf. Zwart 1994) and of the question whether the direct object is moved to or base generated in its formal licensing position. 3 I ignore the question of the exact adjunction position of the adverb in sentences like (4), which in itself yields a potentially significant difference between the two types of analysis in (5). 4 For the multiple specifier hypothesis, the structure in (9b) implies that the [-interpretable] nominal feature of v checked by de race must escape erasure (cf. Chomsky 1995:354). 5 The modal auxiliary zullen, indicating future tense, is included in the embedded clause in order to make sure that the sentence adverb gisteren is construed with the matrix verb,

demonstrating raising into the matrix clause. 6 The negative adverb niet not in (16) is used (just like the adverb gisteren yesterday in (15) and elsewhere) as a matrix clause element indicating that arguments of the embedded clause have been moved to the matrix clause. 7 Obviously, since the assumption that raising verbs lack vp is based on Burzio s Generalization, the burden of proof would be on those wanting to claim the opposite, and the argument as made in the text suffices as a contribution to the discussion regarding the status of agreement projections.