Why `Minimize Restrictor'?

Similar documents
An Introduction to the Minimalist Program

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

SOME MINIMAL NOTES ON MINIMALISM *

Som and Optimality Theory

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

Control and Boundedness

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

The presence of interpretable but ungrammatical sentences corresponds to mismatches between interpretive and productive parsing.

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

LING 329 : MORPHOLOGY

Focusing bound pronouns

LIN 6520 Syntax 2 T 5-6, Th 6 CBD 234

On Labeling: Principle C and Head Movement

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The Inclusiveness Condition in Survive-minimalism

Theoretical Syntax Winter Answers to practice problems

Informatics 2A: Language Complexity and the. Inf2A: Chomsky Hierarchy

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

The Strong Minimalist Thesis and Bounded Optimality

Derivations (MP) and Evaluations (OT) *

Argument structure and theta roles

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

ENGBG1 ENGBL1 Campus Linguistics. Meeting 2. Chapter 7 (Morphology) and chapter 9 (Syntax) Pia Sundqvist

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

Agree or Move? On Partial Control Anna Snarska, Adam Mickiewicz University

Pseudo-Passives as Adjectival Passives

Feature-Based Binding and Phase Theory. A Dissertation Presented. Andrei Antonenko. The Graduate School. in Partial Fulfillment of the.

Interfacing Phonology with LFG

Citation for published version (APA): Veenstra, M. J. A. (1998). Formalizing the minimalist program Groningen: s.n.

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

UCLA UCLA Electronic Theses and Dissertations

Some Principles of Automated Natural Language Information Extraction

CEFR Overall Illustrative English Proficiency Scales

THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & SOCIAL STUDIES

LQVSumm: A Corpus of Linguistic Quality Violations in Multi-Document Summarization

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

The optimal placement of up and ab A comparison 1

When a Complement PP Goes Missing: A Study on the Licensing Condition of Swiping

Specifying Logic Programs in Controlled Natural Language

Phenomena of gender attraction in Polish *

Korean ECM Constructions and Cyclic Linearization

Inleiding Taalkunde. Docent: Paola Monachesi. Blok 4, 2001/ Syntax 2. 2 Phrases and constituent structure 2. 3 A minigrammar of Italian 3

"f TOPIC =T COMP COMP... OBJ

1/20 idea. We ll spend an extra hour on 1/21. based on assigned readings. so you ll be ready to discuss them in class

Second Language Acquisition of Complex Structures: The Case of English Restrictive Relative Clauses

An Interactive Intelligent Language Tutor Over The Internet

Intervention in Tough Constructions * Jeremy Hartman. Massachusetts Institute of Technology

Lecture 9. The Semantic Typology of Indefinites

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

A is an inde nite nominal pro-form that takes antecedents. ere have

The subject of adjectives: Syntactic position and semantic interpretation

The Effect of Extensive Reading on Developing the Grammatical. Accuracy of the EFL Freshmen at Al Al-Bayt University

CHILDREN S POSSESSIVE STRUCTURES: A CASE STUDY 1. Andrew Radford and Joseph Galasso, University of Essex

Chapter 3: Semi-lexical categories. nor truly functional. As Corver and van Riemsdijk rightly point out, There is more

Parsing of part-of-speech tagged Assamese Texts

Phonological and Phonetic Representations: The Case of Neutralization

Prediction of Maximal Projection for Semantic Role Labeling

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Syntax Parsing 1. Grammars and parsing 2. Top-down and bottom-up parsing 3. Chart parsers 4. Bottom-up chart parsing 5. The Earley Algorithm

Parallel Evaluation in Stratal OT * Adam Baker University of Arizona

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

Dependency, licensing and the nature of grammatical relations *

THE INDONESIAN JOURNAL OF LANGUAGE AND LANGUAGE TEACHING

Switched Control and other 'uncontrolled' cases of obligatory control

Lexical Categories and the Projection of Argument Structure

Loughton School s curriculum evening. 28 th February 2017

Pye, C The Focus Antipassive in Quiché Mayan, Kansas University Working Papers in Linguistics.

Advanced Grammar in Use

The semantics of case *

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

Words come in categories

Specification and Evaluation of Machine Translation Toy Systems - Criteria for laboratory assignments

Candidates must achieve a grade of at least C2 level in each examination in order to achieve the overall qualification at C2 Level.

On the Notion Determiner

Update on Soar-based language processing

5 Minimalism and Optimality Theory

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

U : Second Semester French

A Grammar for Battle Management Language

Derivational and Inflectional Morphemes in Pak-Pak Language

THE SHORT ANSWER: IMPLICATIONS FOR DIRECT COMPOSITIONALITY (AND VICE VERSA) Pauline Jacobson. Brown University

Universität Duisburg-Essen

Grammars & Parsing, Part 1:

What Structures Are Underlying Structures?

LTAG-spinal and the Treebank

Aspectual Classes of Verb Phrases

Hindi-Urdu Phrase Structure Annotation

The Structure of Relative Clauses in Maay Maay By Elly Zimmer

Backward Raising. Eric Potsdam and Maria Polinsky. automatically qualify as covert movement. We exclude such operations from consideration here.

Copyright Corwin 2015

Beyond constructions:

Context Free Grammars. Many slides from Michael Collins

Derivational: Inflectional: In a fit of rage the soldiers attacked them both that week, but lost the fight.

Possessive have and (have) got in New Zealand English Heidi Quinn, University of Canterbury, New Zealand

Authors note Chapter One Why Simpler Syntax? 1.1. Different notions of simplicity

Construction Grammar. University of Jena.

Transcription:

Volume 2 Issue 2 Proceedings of the 19th Annual Penn Linguistics Colloquium University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics Article 2 1-1-1995 Why `Minimize Restrictor'? Rajesh Bhatt This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. http://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl/vol2/iss2/2 For more information, please contact libraryrepository@pobox.upenn.edu.

Why `Minimize Restrictor'? This working paper is available in University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics: http://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl/vol2/ iss2/2

Why Minimize Restrictor? Rajesh Bhatt University of Pennsylvania bhatt@linc.cis.upenn.edu 1 Introduction I argue that the framework proposed in Reinhart&Reuland(93) is successfully able to account for Condition B effects which so far had needed a reconstructional analysis. I discuss cases where the Minimize Restrictor condition proposed in Chomsky(92) rules out valid co-indexings. Based on this and some other facts, I propose that the Minimize Restrictor condition is only needed to derive Condition C effects. 2 Background Assumptions In this paper, I utilize the framework proposed by Reinhart&Reuland (1993). This framework consists of the following principles/conditions: (1) [Condition A] A reflexive-marked syntactic predicate is reflexive. (2) [Condition B] A reflexive semantic predicate is reflexive-marked. (3) [Chain Condition] A maximal A-chain ( ) has exactly one link:, which is both +R and marked for structural case and exactly one -marked link. A predicate is reflexive-marked if at least one of its arguments is an anaphor. The conditions A and B of Reinhart&Reuland (1993) reproduce most of the effects of the conditions A and B of GB theory. From this point onwards, I shall refer to conditions A and B of Reinhart&Reuland (1993) as conditions A and B and to conditions A and B of GB theory as A and B. (4) a. * John likes himself. b. * Ed likes him. In (4a), Condition A forces John to be coreferent with the anaphor himself since the presence of an anaphor as an argument of like makes like reflexive. If John and the anaphor are not coindexed, we have a non reflexive reflexive marked predicate which is ruled out by Condition A. Similarly in (4b), Condition B forces Ed to be disjoint with him. If 17

Penn Working Papers in Linguistics Volume 2, no. 2 (1995) Ed and him were coindexed, like which is not reflexive-marked would become a reflexive predicate - this would be ruled out by Condition B. The Chain Condition is however quite different from Condition C of the standard binding theory (Chomsky (1981, 1986a)). So while a sentence like (5) would be ruled out by Condition C, it would not be ruled out by the Chain condition. (5) * She thought that Ed liked Janet. This is not a gap in the framework proposed by Reinhart&Reuland (1993). They consider binding theory to consist only of Conditions A and B, and to govern only bound variable anaphora - Condition C is argued in Reinhart (1983a) and Grodzinsky&Reinhart (1993) to belong to a separate inferential module. 3 Reconstructional Phenomena Reinhart&Reuland(93) note that adopting a theory of logophoric anaphora eliminates the need for reconstruction mechanisms in the case of Condition A. (give page no.) Consider the examples in (6a) and (6b). In both of these the embedded subject Bill can be coindexed with the moved anaphor. Assuming the minimalist assumptions that binding theory conditions apply at LF and also assuming that c-command is one of the relevant conditions, this fact provides evidence that the moved wh-phrase can be construed lower, as the object of the embedded clause at LF. at some (6) a. John wondered [which picture of himself ] [Bill saw t ] b. [Which picture of himself ] does John think Bill likes t? It should be noted that the reconstruction in (6a) and (6b) is optional. The anaphor can be bound by either the matrix or the lower binder reflecting under minimalist assumptions, the LF position of the anaphor. Reinhart & Reuland account for the above data by a very different theoretical device. Note that the definitions of Conditions A and B involve the word predicate. A predicate is formed only when there is an external argument. This captures the intuition seen in several versions of binding theory that there is something special about the Subject. This was reflected in the use of notions such as Accesible Subject. In NPs like which picture of himself, picture does not form a predicate since it does not have an external argument. As a result neither Condition A nor Condition B apply to the anaphor in question - as a result it can act like a logophor and refer freely subject to pragmatic constraints. So in both (6a) and (6b), the anaphor can refer to either the matrix or the embedded subject. Reinhart&Reuland (1993) also note, however, that this does not entail that the problem of reconstruction is eliminated altogether. So far, reconstruction may still be needed for cases of Condition B and C. 18

Why Minimize Restrictor Bhatt In the following sections, I show that we need not appeal to reconstruction to obtain Condition B effects within Reinhart&Reuland (1993). I also show that obligatory reconstruction of the kind enforced by the principle of Minimize Restrictor rules out certain legal coindexings. 3.1 Condition B and reconstruction Based on the examples in (6a) and (6b), Chomsky (1993) claims that we need a conception of binding theory which distinguishes condition A, which does not force reconstruction, from conditions B and C, which do. (7) John wondered [which picture of Tom ] [he liked t ] (8) John wondered [which picture of him ] [Bill took t ] (9) John wondered [what attitude about him ] [Bill had t ] While in (6a) and (6b), the reconstruction was optional (7), (8) and (9) are all cases of obligatory reconstruction. If like in the case of (6a) or (6b) the reconstruction was optional we would expect that in (7), Tom and he can be coreferent. Similarly for (8) and (9). As discussed earlier, in the framework of Reinhart & Reuland (1993) Condition C is not part of the binding theory which only consists of Conditions A, B and the Chain Condition. (7) involves Condition C, hence since I am using the framework of Reinhart & Reuland (1993) I will put it aside for now. My analysis of (8) and (9) starts with the observation that they are both cases of NPs that involve an idiomatic reading - they have also been analyzed as having a PRO subject. Note the contrast in (10a) and (10b). (10) a. John saw [a picture of him ]. b. * John took [a picture of him ]. (11) * John had [an attitude about him ]. Chomsky (1986b) argued that (10b) (or 11) had a structure that contained a PRO element controlled by the matrix subject as shown in (12). (12) * John took [PRO picture of him ]. Thus the standard Condition B rule out the following sentence. The PRO analysis has the problem that while the PRO is needed for the take a picture cases, it s presence in see a picture produces illicit readings. The problem is that if the PRO in a picture of... is obligatory (10a) should be ungrammatical while if it is optional (10b) should be grammatical. The insight being missed is that the presence of PRO/external 19

Penn Working Papers in Linguistics Volume 2, no. 2 (1995) argument of the NP is conditioned by the predicate. This insight is captured by Williams (1985, 1987) implicit arguments analysis. Further Williams (1982, 1985, 1987) has argued that such a PRO analysis is not feasible - these apparent control effects surface even where a PRO is not possible. Instead he proposes that the N-agent role which is not syntactically realized, is satisfied in the lexicon and can get a referential value either by control or from the context. Cf. (10b) and (11) Chomsky (1993) does not use the PRO solution and instead argues that the idiomatic reading is available only when take...picture forms a unit at LF. This can be seen in the (minimalist) LFs for (8) and (9) given in (13a) and (13b) respectively: (13) a. John wondered [which x][bill took [x picture of him ]](LF for (8)) b. John wondered [what x][bill had [x attitude about him ]](LF for (9)) The notion of unit at LF refers to string contiguity at LF. Chomsky(92) rules out LFs like (14a) by having a principle called Minimize Restrictor - minimize the restrictor wherever you can - This principle forces reconstruction in all Condition B and C environments. (14) a. # John wondered [which picture of him x][bill took [x ]] b. John wondered [which x][bill took [x picture of him]] (14a) is ruled out because of the existence of the convergent (14b) where the restrictor has been minimized. Both (8) and (9) can be handled within Reinhart&Reuland(93) - these are both examples where the lexical semantics of the verb causes the N-agent roles of the noun to be instantiated as identical to the agent of the verb. Now Condition B is enough to rule out any coindexing between Bill and him since this would cause the semantic predicate picture to be reflexive even though it is not reflexive-marked. Requiring Minimize Restrictor to apply in all Condition B environments seems to be too strong as it rules out several cases of legal coindexation. Consider (15). (15) Mary wondered [which picture of him ] [Bill submitted t for the fashion show]. If the restrictor needed to be minimized in all cases, (15) would be out since it would have the LF in (16): (16) Mary wondered [which x] [Bill submitted [x picture of him] for the fashion show]. (16) violates the standard binding condition B and hence (15) should be ungrammatical. A PRO analysis would get us (15) but would have problems as discussed earlier with sentences like (17). (17) * Mary wondered [which picture of him ] Bill took t for the fashion show. If the picture NP had a PRO (15) could have the following legal LF: 20

Why Minimize Restrictor Bhatt (18) Mary wondered [which x] [Bill submitted [x PRO picture of him ] for the fashion show]. However this would lead us to expect the grammaticality of the ungrammatical (17) since it would have an LF very similar to (18). This problem arises, as discussed before, because the relationship between take and the picture-np is not taken into consideration. Reinhart & Reuland (1993) are able to account for this reading. take instantiates the implicit argument of the picture-np as its agent and thus causes the formation of a nonreflexive marked reflexive predicate and hence a Condition B violation. The lexical semantics of submit are different and coindexing the pronoun in the picture-np with the agent of submit does not lead to a Condition B violation. 3.2 Reconstruction for Interpretation In the previous section, we have seen that we do not need a special operation of reconstruction to derive Condition B binding effects. Further in the case of Condition B, reconstruction is obligatory only in idiomatic environments such as take a picture. Reconstruction for reasons of interpretation is however not ruled out. Cf.(19) (19) Who wanted John to destroy how many pictures that he had painted? Heycock (1993)(following Kroch (1989)) claims that (19) has two readings: a nonreferential reading(lf in (20a) and a referential, non D-linked reading(lf in (20b)). (20) a. [How many x][who y] y wanted John to destroy [x pictures that he had painted] b. [How many pictures that he had painted x][who y] y wanted John to destroy [x] With minimization of restrictor, (20b) would not be a legal LF. However, the reading in (20b) does seem to be available. If following the argumentation in Kroch (1989) we assume that the LF in (20b) is the correct representation for the referential, non D-linked reading then Minimize Restrictor would rule out such representations a-priori. This does not seem desirable. 3.3 Problems with anaphors In Chomsky (1993), Condition A environments such as (21a) do not obligatorily reconstruct because the anaphor can cliticize to the matrix verb yielding the (non reconstructing) LF in (21b): (21) a. John wondered [which picture of himself] [Bill likes t ] b. John self-wondered [which picture of t x] [Bill likes x] 21

Penn Working Papers in Linguistics Volume 2, no. 2 (1995) Minimizing the restrictor will lead to deletion of t, breaking the chain (self, t ) and leaving the reflexive element without a -role at LF. A reconstructing derivation also exists(22), in which the anaphor cliticizes onto likes. (22) John wondered [which x][bill self-likes [x pictures of t ]]. The crucial thing is that LF-cliticization of the anaphor is deemed sufficient to block Minimize Restrictor - It is ranked below other principles. If there are two convergent derivations from the same numeration only one of which minimizes restrictor, then the one with the minimized restrictor blocks the other. However if the derivation crashes as a result of minimizing restrictor, then it is legal not to minimize restrictor. There are some conceptual problems with this approach. Consider the (illegal) reconstructing derivation in which self cliticizes to wonder and we also minimize restrictor: (23) John self-wondered [which x] [Bill likes x picture of self] Note that since in the minimalist program, we have a copy theory of movement, the lower copy is left intact - the upper copy which had had movement of self out of it is deleted since we are minimizing restrictor. While it is clear that (23) is an illegitimate derivation, it is not clear whether this derivation is bad because it converges as semi-gibberish at LF(no -role for self) or because it crashes. In order to allow the non-reconstructing derivation to get through we have to stipulate that it crashes. That this is so is non-obvious. Further consider (24) where the same ambiguity obtains: (24) [Which picture of himself ] does John think [ Bill likes t ] Minimizing restrictor with self cliticized to the embedded predicate like gives us the reading where the anaphor is coindexed within the embedded clause. Applying LF-cliticization from the landing site leads to a lowering movement: such movements result in an ungoverned trace and there is considerable evidence that suggests that such movements should not be permitted at all. On the other hand applying LF-cliticization from the position of the intermediate trace creates an illicit LF. Further it is not clear if intermediate traces exist at LF. Considering the close similarity between (24) (21a), we expect an analysis given for (21a) to carry over to (24). The LF-cliticization analysis does not do well on this account. Reinhart &Reuland (1993) are able to explain this straightforwardly and also capture the similarity between (21a) and (24). In both (21a) and (24), the anaphor is in a picture-np where predicate formation does not take place. As a result, it can act as a logophor and refer freely constrained only by discourse. 4 So where do we need Minimize Restrictor? Minimize Restrictor is still needed to derive Condition C effects as in (25a) and (25b). 22

Why Minimize Restrictor Bhatt (25) a. John wondered [which picture of Tom ] [he liked t ] b. * Who wanted him to destroy how many pictures that John had painted? 5 Conclusions We see that Minimize Restrictor is not needed to derive Condition A and B effects. Adopting Reinhart & Reuland (1993) s framework allows us to account for these cases without having special rules of reconstruction like Minimize Restrictor. Further it is not just redundant but also problematic since it rules out certain LFs which are independently motivated. Its basic purpose is to drive LF-lowering of R-expressions to feed Condition C violations.(see Heycock (1993)) The existence of a principle such as Minimize Restrictor is puzzling since some kind of least effort principle would work in the opposite direction and would argue for maximization of restrictor since it is easily demonstratable that pruning the search space at the source makes for a more efficient search strategy. The fact that Conditions A and B pattern together in not needing Minimize Restrictor versus Condition C which does and the fact that Conditions A and B are in a sense local while condition C is non-local. suggests that treating the binding theory as only consisting of Conditions A and B is on the right track. Then if Minimize Restrictor was part of the grammar, it would be part of the same inferential module to which Condition C belongs. References [1] N. Chomsky. Lectures on Government and Binding. Foris, Dordrecht, 1981. [2] N. Chomsky. Knowledge of Language:Its nature origin and use. Praeger, New York, 1986. [3] Noam Chomsky. A Minimalist Program for Linguistic Theory. In Kenneth Hale and Samuel Jay Keyser, editors, The View from Building 20. MIT Press, 1993. [4] Caroline Heycock. Reconstructing Referentiality. Technical report, Department of Linguistics, Yale University, New Haven, CT, 1993. [5] Hilda Koopman and Dominique Sportiche. Pronouns, Logical Variables, and Logophoricity in Abe. Linguistic Inquiry, 20:555 588, 1989. [6] Tanya Reinhart and Eric Reuland. Reflexivity. Linguistic Inquiry, 24:657 720, 1993. [7] Spyridoula Varlokosta and Norbert Hornstein. A Bound Pronoun in Modern Greek. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 9:175 195, 1993. 23

Penn Working Papers in Linguistics Volume 2, no. 2 (1995) [8] Edwin Williams. PRO and subject of NP. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 3:297 315, 1985. [9] Edwin Williams. Implicit arguments, the binding theory and control. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 5:151 180, 1987. 24