Modality, Coherence and Logic

Similar documents
Segmented Discourse Representation Theory. Dynamic Semantics with Discourse Structure

Lecture 9. The Semantic Typology of Indefinites

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

Philosophy 301L: Early Modern Philosophy, Spring 2012

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

PAGE(S) WHERE TAUGHT If sub mission ins not a book, cite appropriate location(s))

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

Writing a composition

The Evolution of Random Phenomena

CAN PICTORIAL REPRESENTATIONS SUPPORT PROPORTIONAL REASONING? THE CASE OF A MIXING PAINT PROBLEM

Parallel Evaluation in Stratal OT * Adam Baker University of Arizona

Transitive meanings for intransitive verbs

The Discourse Anaphoric Properties of Connectives

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & SOCIAL STUDIES

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

The Use of Lexical Cohesion in Reading and Writing

Shared Content (Draft)

Construction Grammar. University of Jena.

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Mini Lesson Ideas for Expository Writing

THE ANTINOMY OF THE VARIABLE: A TARSKIAN RESOLUTION Bryan Pickel and Brian Rabern University of Edinburgh

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Lecture 2: Quantifiers and Approximation

Genevieve L. Hartman, Ph.D.

Linguistic Inquiry, Volume 35, Number 1, Winter 2004, pp (Article)

The Effect of Extensive Reading on Developing the Grammatical. Accuracy of the EFL Freshmen at Al Al-Bayt University

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

Interpreting Vague Utterances in Context

Syllabus for Philosophy of Mathematics Thomas Donaldson; Winter Quarter, 2015

a) analyse sentences, so you know what s going on and how to use that information to help you find the answer.

NAME: East Carolina University PSYC Developmental Psychology Dr. Eppler & Dr. Ironsmith

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

PHILOSOPHY & CULTURE Syllabus

Past, Present, and Future Tenses. Language Presentation by Mark

Rule-based Expert Systems

5 th Grade Language Arts Curriculum Map

A Coding System for Dynamic Topic Analysis: A Computer-Mediated Discourse Analysis Technique

Aspectual Classes of Verb Phrases

AN ANALYSIS OF GRAMMTICAL ERRORS MADE BY THE SECOND YEAR STUDENTS OF SMAN 5 PADANG IN WRITING PAST EXPERIENCES

Myths, Legends, Fairytales and Novels (Writing a Letter)

Transfer Learning Action Models by Measuring the Similarity of Different Domains

In how many ways can one junior and one senior be selected from a group of 8 juniors and 6 seniors?

Informatics 2A: Language Complexity and the. Inf2A: Chomsky Hierarchy

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

5. UPPER INTERMEDIATE

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

STT 231 Test 1. Fill in the Letter of Your Choice to Each Question in the Scantron. Each question is worth 2 point.

Today we examine the distribution of infinitival clauses, which can be

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

The Task. A Guide for Tutors in the Rutgers Writing Centers Written and edited by Michael Goeller and Karen Kalteissen

Evaluating Statements About Probability

Specifying Logic Programs in Controlled Natural Language

Unit Lesson Plan: Native Americans 4th grade (SS and ELA)

ELA/ELD Standards Correlation Matrix for ELD Materials Grade 1 Reading

Developing a concrete-pictorial-abstract model for negative number arithmetic

Discourse Processing for Explanatory Essays in Tutorial Applications

Subject: Opening the American West. What are you teaching? Explorations of Lewis and Clark

Monsters and the theoretical role of context

Key concepts for the insider-researcher

Candidates must achieve a grade of at least C2 level in each examination in order to achieve the overall qualification at C2 Level.

CEFR Overall Illustrative English Proficiency Scales

Shared Mental Models

Linguistics 220 Phonology: distributions and the concept of the phoneme. John Alderete, Simon Fraser University

Grade 11 Language Arts (2 Semester Course) CURRICULUM. Course Description ENGLISH 11 (2 Semester Course) Duration: 2 Semesters Prerequisite: None

5 Star Writing Persuasive Essay

Interpretive (seeing) Interpersonal (speaking and short phrases)

Types and Lexical Semantics

Formulaic Language and Fluency: ESL Teaching Applications

Experience Corps. Mentor Toolkit

Intension, Attitude, and Tense Annotation in a High-Fidelity Semantic Representation

Loughton School s curriculum evening. 28 th February 2017

Albert Einstein High School s 45 th Birthday Crewcuts and Bobby Socks

Eliciting Language in the Classroom. Presented by: Dionne Ramey, SBCUSD SLP Amanda Drake, SBCUSD Special Ed. Program Specialist

- «Crede Experto:,,,». 2 (09) ( '36

A Grammar for Battle Management Language

THE SHORT ANSWER: IMPLICATIONS FOR DIRECT COMPOSITIONALITY (AND VICE VERSA) Pauline Jacobson. Brown University

The Effect of Discourse Markers on the Speaking Production of EFL Students. Iman Moradimanesh

Language specific preferences in anaphor resolution: Exposure or gricean maxims?

Part I. Figuring out how English works

Handouts and Resources

Control and Boundedness

Conteúdos de inglês para o primeiro bimestre. Turma 21. Turma 31. Turma 41

Foundations of Knowledge Representation in Cyc

A Correlation of. Grade 6, Arizona s College and Career Ready Standards English Language Arts and Literacy

UNIT IX. Don t Tell. Are there some things that grown-ups don t let you do? Read about what this child feels.

Evolution of Collective Commitment during Teamwork

The Short Essay: Week 6

Thornhill Primary School - Grammar coverage Year 1-6

Speak with Confidence The Art of Developing Presentations & Impromptu Speaking

WHAT ARE VIRTUAL MANIPULATIVES?

Managerial Decision Making

The Writing Process. The Academic Support Centre // September 2015

National University of Singapore Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences Centre for Language Studies Academic Year 2014/2015 Semester 2

Introduction 1 MBTI Basics 2 Decision-Making Applications 44 How to Get the Most out of This Booklet 6

Grade 2: Using a Number Line to Order and Compare Numbers Place Value Horizontal Content Strand

Mastering Team Skills and Interpersonal Communication. Copyright 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. publishing as Prentice Hall.

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY: PER COURSE TEACHING POSITIONS Spring, 2017

Left, Left, Left, Right, Left

Transcription:

Modality, Coherence and Logic Una Stojnić Rutgers University Bridges 2 September 18, 2015

Pronouns and Modals An Analogy Mechanisms for Resolving Context-Sensitivity Under the Hood Summing Up

The Counterexample (Yalcin, 2012) There s an urn with a 100 marbles. 10 of them are big and blue, 30 big and red, 50 small and blue, and 10 are small and red. One marble is randomly selected and hidden (you do not know which). 1. If the marble is big, then it is likely red. 2. But, the marble is not likely red. 3. The marble is not big.

The Counterexample (Yalcin, 2012) There s an urn with a 100 marbles. 10 of them are big and blue, 30 big and red, 50 small and blue, and 10 are small and red. One marble is randomly selected and hidden (you do not know which). 1. If the marble is big, then it is likely red. 2. But, the marble is not likely red. 3. The marble is not big.

Counterexample Reactions MT is invalid! Resist! It s not merely a matter of conservativeness. This opens the flood-gates.

Counterexample Reactions MT is invalid! Resist! It s not merely a matter of conservativeness. This opens the flood-gates.

Proliferation of Counterexamples There s an urn with 100 marbles. 10 of them are big and blue, 30 big and red, 50 small and blue, and 10 are small and red. One marble is randomly selected and hidden (you do not know which). 4. Suppose the marble is big. 5. Then it is likely red. 6. But it s not likely red. 7. So, it is not big.

Proliferation of Counterexamples There s an urn with 100 marbles. We know that 80 of them are blue, 18 are red and 2 are green. One marble is randomly selected and hidden (you do not know which). 8. The marble is either blue or it is likely red. 9. Suppose that the marble is not blue. 10. Then, it is likely red. 11. But the marble is not likely red. 12. So, it is blue.

Proliferation of Counterexamples There s an urn with 100 marbles. We know that 80 of them are blue, 18 are red and 2 are green. One marble is randomly selected and hidden (you do not know which). 8. The marble is either blue or it is likely red. 9. Suppose that the marble is not blue. 10. Then, it is likely red. 11. But the marble is not likely red. 12. So, it is blue.

Counterexample Reactions MT is invalid! (1) (3) is not an instance of MT.

Obligatory Wide-Scoping 13. Likely (if the marble is big, the it is red.) 14. But, the marble is not likely red. 15. The marble is not big.

Obligatory Wide-Scoping 16. If Bill comes to the party, then if John comes, it is likely that Margaret will come, too. 17. It is likely that if Bill comes then if John, comes Margaret will come.

Counterexample Reactions MT is invalid! 4 6 is not an instance of MT. Obligatory Wide-Scoping. Context-sensitivity at play.

Context-sensitivity ad hoc? 18. If John drank all the milk, then the fridge is empty. 19. But the fridge is not empty. 20. So John didn t drink all the milk. 21. If Billy is 6 5 tall, he is tall. 22. But Billy is not tall. 23. So, Billy is not 6 5 tall.

Pronouns and Modals An Analogy Mechanisms for Resolving Context-Sensitivity Under the Hood Summing Up

A Counterexample? 24. If Jane is out, then she is having fun. 25. She (pointing at Mary) is not having fun. 26. So Jane is not out.

A Counterexample? As usual, Mary is stuck at home doing chores, jealous of Jane, who s always having more fun then she is. 27. If Jane is out, then she is having fun. 28. But she is not having fun. 29. So Jane is not out.

Pronouns and Modals An Analogy Mechanisms for Resolving Context-Sensitivity Under the Hood Summing Up

Coherence 30. John took a train from Paris to Istanbul. He has family there. 31. John took a train from Paris to Istanbul. He likes spinach. (Hobbs, 1979) An implicit organization of discourse establishes inferential connections among successive utterances. Successive contributions to discourse must be linked together by a recognizable flow of interpretive relationships. (Kehler 2002; Asher and Lascarides 2003)

Coherence, (Kehler, 2002) Cause-effect: 32. Max spilt a bucket of water. He tripped over his shoelaces. Occasion: 33. Max spilt a bucket of water. He spilt it all over the rug. Resemblance: 34. Max spilt a bucket of water. John dropped a jar of cookies.

Coherence and Pronoun Resolution 35. Phil tickled Stanley. Liz poked him.(kehler et al., 2008) result him = Phil. parallel him = Stanley. The problems of identifying coherence relations and resolving semantic ambiguities are mutually constraining.

Coherence and Pronoun Resolution: An Illustration 22. If Jane is out, then she is having fun. 23. She is not having fun. 24. So Jane is not out. She in 22 is uttered in an elaboration concerning Jane s state, it is resolved to Jane. If 23 is uttered in tandem with a pointing gesture, she refers to the individual being pointed at.

Modals as Pronouns 36. She left me. (Partee, 1984) 37. My neighbors would kill me. (Stone, 1997) 38. John owns a donkey. He beats it. 39. There may be other 1961 state committee retirements come April 18, but they will be leaving by choice of the Republican voters. (Stone, 1997)

Modals as Pronouns 36. She left me. (Partee, 1984) 37. My neighbors would kill me. (Stone, 1997) 38. John owns a donkey. He beats it. 39. There may be other 1961 state committee retirements come April 18, but they will be leaving by choice of the Republican voters. (Stone, 1997)

Modals as Pronouns 40. Every woman believes that she is happy. (Partee, 1984) 41. If a concert goer arrives late, he or she will not be permitted into the auditorium. (Stone, 1997) 42. If John owns a donkey, he beats it. 43. If a submarine can not self-destruct if an enemy captures it, the enemy will learn its secrets. (Stone, 1997) Interpretation of modals is an anaphoric process, just as the interpretation of tense and pronouns is. (Stone, 1997, 1999)

Modals as Pronouns 40. Every woman believes that she is happy. (Partee, 1984) 41. If a concert goer arrives late, he or she will not be permitted into the auditorium. (Stone, 1997) 42. If John owns a donkey, he beats it. 43. If a submarine can not self-destruct if an enemy captures it, the enemy will learn its secrets. (Stone, 1997) Interpretation of modals is an anaphoric process, just as the interpretation of tense and pronouns is. (Stone, 1997, 1999)

Modals as Pronouns 40. Every woman believes that she is happy. (Partee, 1984) 41. If a concert goer arrives late, he or she will not be permitted into the auditorium. (Stone, 1997) 42. If John owns a donkey, he beats it. 43. If a submarine can not self-destruct if an enemy captures it, the enemy will learn its secrets. (Stone, 1997) Interpretation of modals is an anaphoric process, just as the interpretation of tense and pronouns is. (Stone, 1997, 1999)

Coherence and Modals 44. If a wolf walks in, it might eat Harvey. (Roberts, 1989) 45. A wolf might walk in. It would eat you first. (Roberts, 1989) 46. Sally is hiding because I might be on the bus. (Cappelen and Hawthorne, 2009) 47. If a wolf walks in, it would eat you. But, one probably won t/might not come in. 48. John might come to the party. He might drink quite a bit. We would all have fun. But then again, he might not drink anything. And then we wouldn t have fun. (Asher and McCready, 2007)

The Counterexample Reconsidered 4. If the marble is big, then it is likely red. 5. But, the marble is not likely red. 6. The marble is not big. If Contrast holds between 5 and the consequent of 4, then likely is quantifying over the same set of worlds as the one in the consequent of 4. If 4 and 5 are related by Contrast, then the two occurrence of likely quantify over different sets of worlds.

Pronouns and Modals An Analogy Mechanisms for Resolving Context-Sensitivity Under the Hood Summing Up

Key Ideas We treat modals as anaphoric expressions, searching for the most prominent set of worlds (possibility) as their antecedent. Standard: might(q) = {w w : wrw & w q} (Kratzer, 1977, 1981) Stojnić: might(p, q) = {w w : wrw & w p & w q}

Key Ideas We treat modals as anaphoric expressions, searching for the most prominent set of worlds (possibility) as their antecedent. Standard: might(q) = {w w : wrw & w q} (Kratzer, 1977, 1981) Stojnić: might(p, q) = {w w : wrw & w p & w q}

Key Ideas We treat modals as anaphoric expressions, searching for the most prominent set of worlds (possibility) as their antecedent. Standard: might(q) = {w w : wrw & w q} (Kratzer, 1977, 1981) Stojnić: might(p, q) = {w w : wrw & w p & w q}

Key Ideas Let the context include the prominence ranking of candidate possibilities; discourse initially, the top ranked-one = the set of epistemically accessible worlds. Linguistic items mark updates that affect the ranking.

Yalcin s Counterexample Formalized 1. If the marble is big, then it s likely red. 2. But, the marble is not likely red. 49. Contrast(Assert(If(@p, arg 0 /p, Elab(w 0, Likely(@p, arg 0 /q )))); Assert(Not(Likley(@p, arg 0 /q )))) @p denotes the set of top-ranked epistemically accessible worlds (top-ranked possibility). p corresponds to the marble is big and q to the marble is red.

Pronouns and Modals An Analogy Mechanisms for Resolving Context-Sensitivity Under the Hood Summing Up

Summing Up: I have argued... Modals are like pronouns in two crucial respects: they are anaphoric expressions, and they are sensitive to exactly the same interpretive mechanisms of anaphora resolution as pronouns are. The counterexamples arise due to a failure to appreciate the import of mechanisms that govern the resolution of context-sensitivity of modals (just as they do with pronouns). The lesson is not that modal vocabulary requires a non-standard semantics but rather that discourse structuring mechanisms affect interpretation, and they do so in a highly systematic manner. (As I prove in the written version) the underlying logic preserves classical logic.

Thank you!

Bibliography I Asher, Nicholas and Lascarides, Alex. 2003. Logics of Conversation. Cambridge University Press. Asher, Nicholas and McCready, Eric. 2007. Were, Would, Might and a Compositional Account of Counterfactuals. Journal of Semantics 24:93 129. Cappelen, Herman and Hawthorne, John. 2009. Relativism and Monadic Truth. Oxford University Press. Hobbs, Jerry R. 1979. Coherence and Coreference. Congitive Science 3:67 90. Kehler, Andrew. 2002. Coherence, Reference and the Theory of Grammar. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications. Kehler, Andrew, Kertz, Laura, Rohde, Hannah, and Elman, Jeffrey L. 2008. Coherence and Coreference Revisited. Journal of Semantics 25:1 44.

Bibliography II Kratzer, Angelika. 1977. What Must and Can Must and Can Mean. Linguistics and Philosophy 1:337 355.. 1981. Notional Cateogry of Modality. In H. J. Einkmeyer and H. Rieser (eds.), Words, Worlds, and Contexts: New Approaches in Word Semantics, 38 74. Berlin: de Gruyeter. Partee, Barbara. 1984. Nominal and Temporal Anaphora. Linguistics and Philosophy 7:243 286. Roberts, Craige. 1989. Modal Subordination and Pronominal Anaphora in Discourse. Linguistics and Philosophy 12:683 721. Stone, Matthew. 1997. The Anaphoric Parallel Between Modality and Tense. IRCS Report 97-06.. 1999. Reference to Possible Worlds. RuCCS Report 49., Rutgers University, New Brunswick. Yalcin, Seth. 2012. A Counterexample to Modus Tollens. Journal of Philosophical Logic 41:1001 1024.