Deirdre Wilson and Dan Sperber. Preface and Table of Contents of Meaning and Relevance, Cambridge University Press Preface

Similar documents
Procedural pragmatics and the study of discourse Louis de Saussure

Does Linguistic Communication Rest on Inference?

Relevance Theory and the saying/implicating distinction *

Oakland Unified School District English/ Language Arts Course Syllabus

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

Oakland Unified School District English/ Language Arts Course Syllabus

PAGE(S) WHERE TAUGHT If sub mission ins not a book, cite appropriate location(s))

1. APPROACHING OVERSTATEMENT

CEFR Overall Illustrative English Proficiency Scales

Arizona s English Language Arts Standards th Grade ARIZONA DEPARTMENT OF EDUCATION HIGH ACADEMIC STANDARDS FOR STUDENTS

Document number: 2013/ Programs Committee 6/2014 (July) Agenda Item 42.0 Bachelor of Engineering with Honours in Software Engineering

Applications of Relevance Theory

Specification and Evaluation of Machine Translation Toy Systems - Criteria for laboratory assignments

Think A F R I C A when assessing speaking. C.E.F.R. Oral Assessment Criteria. Think A F R I C A - 1 -

Abstractions and the Brain

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Is pragmatics of discourse possible?

Achievement Level Descriptors for American Literature and Composition

MEASURING ORDINARY MEANING USING SURVEYS JP SEVILLA 3L and Levy Fellow George Mason University School of Law September 10, 2014

TAG QUESTIONS" Department of Language and Literature - University of Birmingham

Night by Elie Wiesel. Standards Link:

1. Answer the questions below on the Lesson Planning Response Document.

AN INTRODUCTION (2 ND ED.) (LONDON, BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC PP. VI, 282)

English Language Arts Missouri Learning Standards Grade-Level Expectations

The Effect of Discourse Markers on the Speaking Production of EFL Students. Iman Moradimanesh

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

California Department of Education English Language Development Standards for Grade 8

The Pragmatics of Imperative and Declarative Pointing 1

Rubric for Scoring English 1 Unit 1, Rhetorical Analysis

A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF MINNESOTA BY. Kaitlin Rose Johnson

Highlighting and Annotation Tips Foundation Lesson

MA Linguistics Language and Communication

THE USE OF ENGLISH MOVIE IN TEACHING AUSTIN S ACT

A Case Study: News Classification Based on Term Frequency

Common Core State Standards for English Language Arts

Key concepts for the insider-researcher

Grade 11 Language Arts (2 Semester Course) CURRICULUM. Course Description ENGLISH 11 (2 Semester Course) Duration: 2 Semesters Prerequisite: None

I N T E R P R E T H O G A N D E V E L O P HOGAN BUSINESS REASONING INVENTORY. Report for: Martina Mustermann ID: HC Date: May 02, 2017

Scoring Guide for Candidates For retake candidates who began the Certification process in and earlier.

Metadiscourse in Knowledge Building: A question about written or verbal metadiscourse

Realization of Textual Cohesion and Coherence in Business Letters through Presupposition 1

prehending general textbooks, but are unable to compensate these problems on the micro level in comprehending mathematical texts.

Express, an International Journal of Multi Disciplinary Research ISSN: , Vol. 1, Issue 3, March 2014 Available at: journal.

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

This Performance Standards include four major components. They are

Describing Motion Events in Adult L2 Spanish Narratives

Problems with the implementation of Research-Based Teacher Education Reform 1

Literature and the Language Arts Experiencing Literature

Pennsylvania Common Core Standards English Language Arts Grade 11

A cautionary note is research still caught up in an implementer approach to the teacher?

NAME OF ASSESSMENT: Reading Informational Texts and Argument Writing Performance Assessment

Higher education is becoming a major driver of economic competitiveness

Language Acquisition Chart

Practical Research. Planning and Design. Paul D. Leedy. Jeanne Ellis Ormrod. Upper Saddle River, New Jersey Columbus, Ohio

Program Matrix - Reading English 6-12 (DOE Code 398) University of Florida. Reading

10.2. Behavior models

2006 Mississippi Language Arts Framework-Revised Grade 12

Ling/Span/Fren/Ger/Educ 466: SECOND LANGUAGE ACQUISITION. Spring 2011 (Tuesdays 4-6:30; Psychology 251)

Mental Models and the Meaning of Connectives: A Study on Children, Adolescents and Adults

CMST 2060 Public Speaking

Prentice Hall Literature Common Core Edition Grade 10, 2012

Teaching digital literacy in sub-saharan Africa ICT as separate subject

5. UPPER INTERMEDIATE

Gricean Communication and Transmission of Thoughts

Interpreting Vague Utterances in Context

TUCSON CAMPUS SCHOOL OF BUSINESS SYLLABUS

INNOWIZ: A GUIDING FRAMEWORK FOR PROJECTS IN INDUSTRIAL DESIGN EDUCATION

Davidson College Library Strategic Plan

RED 3313 Language and Literacy Development course syllabus Dr. Nancy Marshall Associate Professor Reading and Elementary Education

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

Degree Qualification Profiles Intellectual Skills

Stacks Teacher notes. Activity description. Suitability. Time. AMP resources. Equipment. Key mathematical language. Key processes

TOURISM ECONOMICS AND POLICY (ASPECTS OF TOURISM) BY LARRY DWYER, PETER FORSYTH, WAYNE DWYER

- «Crede Experto:,,,». 2 (09) ( '36

South Carolina English Language Arts

Towards a Systematic Approach to Reviewing Literature for Interpreting Public and Business Management Research Results

Ontological spine, localization and multilingual access

AP PSYCHOLOGY VACATION WORK PACKET UNIT 7A: MEMORY

EXAMPLES OF SPEAKING PERFORMANCES AT CEF LEVELS A2 TO C2. (Taken from Cambridge ESOL s Main Suite exams)

TRUST AND RISK IN GAMES OF PARTIAL INFORMATION

Prentice Hall Literature: Timeless Voices, Timeless Themes Gold 2000 Correlated to Nebraska Reading/Writing Standards, (Grade 9)

Certificate of Higher Education in History. Relevant QAA subject benchmarking group: History

ANT4034: HISTORY OF ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY Spring 2014 Syllabus

Discourse-Cognition-Society

Flouting Maxims in Conversational Implicature in The Ellen Degeneres Talk Show

PHILOSOPHY & CULTURE Syllabus

Evolution of Symbolisation in Chimpanzees and Neural Nets

Master s Programme in European Studies

To appear in The TESOL encyclopedia of ELT (Wiley-Blackwell) 1 RECASTING. Kazuya Saito. Birkbeck, University of London

Copyright Corwin 2015

ENGLISH. Progression Chart YEAR 8

Beyond Bourdieu and Bernstein:

Prentice Hall Literature: Timeless Voices, Timeless Themes, Platinum 2000 Correlated to Nebraska Reading/Writing Standards (Grade 10)

PUBLIC SCHOOLS OF EDISON TOWNSHIP DIVISION OF CURRICULUM AND INSTRUCTION LLD LANGUAGE ARTS

The Strong Minimalist Thesis and Bounded Optimality

University of Toronto

An Introduction to the Minimalist Program

Module 12. Machine Learning. Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Teaching Task Rewrite. Teaching Task: Rewrite the Teaching Task: What is the theme of the poem Mother to Son?

Introduction. 1. Evidence-informed teaching Prelude

Transcription:

Preface and Table of Contents of Meaning and Relevance, Cambridge University Press 2012 Preface When Mary speaks to Peter, she has a certain meaning in mind that she intends to convey: say, that the plumber she just called is on his way. To convey this meaning, she utters certain words: say, He will arrive in a minute. What is the relation between Mary s intended meaning and the linguistic meaning of her utterance? A simple (indeed simplistic) view is that for every intended meaning there is a sentence with an identical linguistic meaning, so that conveying a meaning is just a matter of encoding it into a matching verbal form, which the hearer decodes back into the corresponding linguistic meaning. But, at least in practice, this is not what happens. There are always components of a speaker s meaning which her words do not encode. For instance, the English word he does not specifically refer to the plumber Mary is talking about. Indeed, the idea that for most, if not all, possible meanings that a speaker might intend to convey, there is a sentence in a natural language which has that exact meaning as its linguistic meaning is quite implausible. An apparently more realistic view is that the speaker typically produces an utterance which encodes some, but not all, of her meaning. Certain components of her meaning for instance, in Mary s utterance the referent of he or the place where he will arrive are not encoded, and have to be inferred by the hearer. While it might seem that a speaker s meaning should in principle be fully encodable, attempts to achieve such a full encoding in practice leave an unencoded, and perhaps unencodable, residue. We have been arguing for a long time that this widely accepted view is still too simple, and that utterances do not encode the speaker s meaning not even some of it. The function of the linguistic meaning of an utterance is not to encode the speaker s meaning, but

to provide evidence of her meaning. For instance, when Mary says that the plumber will arrive in a minute, the linguistic meaning of the phrase a minute is not part of her intended meaning. Mary uses this expression not to encode her meaning, but merely to indicate to Peter that she means an amount of time as trivial in the circumstances as a minute would be. In more standard approaches, this use of language would be treated as a case of hyperbole and analysed, along with metaphor and irony, as a departure from the normal practice of using the linguistic meanings of words to encode the speaker s intended meaning. We have argued that hyperbole, metaphor and irony are normal uses of language, which involve no special device or procedure. If we are right, then the goal of pragmatics the study of utterance comprehension in context is to investigate an inferential process which takes as input the production of an utterance by a speaker, on the one hand, and contextual information, on the other, and yields as output an interpretation of the speaker s intended meaning. We believe that inferential processes are best approached from the perspective of cognitive psychology, with the tools provided by that framework. For that reason, we have put forward hypotheses about the basic cognitive dispositions and mechanisms recruited in utterance interpretation, and have promoted the development of experimental pragmatics (see Noveck and Sperber 2004). Pragmatics not only stands to benefit from cognitive psychology, but can also contribute to it in worthwhile ways. Among higher cognitive processes, pragmatic processes are of special interest because their inputs and outputs are highly structured and complex, yet we are in a position to give rich and precise descriptions of at least the linguistic components of these inputs, thanks to the development of linguistics, and in particular of semantics. In fact, the formalisation of semantics is so far advanced that there is a temptation to try and approach pragmatics as an extension of formal semantics, raising similar problems, to be tackled using similar methods. In our view, this can only be done at the price of

abandoning or at least backgrounding the cognitive psychology framework, and idealising away the most fundamental aspect of pragmatics, which is the joint inferential processing of an utterance and an open-ended context (this rather reminds us of the way methodological rigour was achieved in behaviourist psychology by idealising away the mental). We repeat: pragmatics is first and foremost about a process, and not about a set of abstract formal relationships between linguistic meaning, context and intended meaning. Moreover, the context used in utterance comprehension is vast and open-ended. Understanding how a context of this type can be exploited and coordinated across interlocutors is a crucial problem for pragmatics, which is bypassed when the context is idealised into a small closed set of items. While we are open to semantic solutions to apparently pragmatic problems, we believe that Paul Grice, the founder of modern pragmatics, was right to argue that many semantic problems have more parsimonious pragmatic solutions. In any case, if, as we claim, linguistic meanings are used not to encode the speaker s meaning but merely to provide evidence of it, then the relation between semantics and pragmatics will have to be rethought, and in a more systematic and constructive way than the current series of border skirmishes and sorties. In our 1986 book Relevance: Communication and Cognition, we described in some detail a cognitive approach to pragmatics, relevance theory, which this book revisits, updates and expands. Since then, work on relevance theory has become a collective endeavour, with more than thirty books let us just mention the most deservedly influential of them, Robyn Carston s Thoughts and Utterances (2002) and hundreds of articles in linguistics, psychology, philosophy and literary studies. The theory has been widely debated, with occasional misunderstandings and caricatures, but also highly relevant comments, for which we are grateful. Apart from a Postface to the 1995 second edition of Relevance which revised and clarified some basic assumptions, we ourselves have contributed to the development of the

theory through a series of articles written together, singly, or with other collaborators. We have selected for this volume what we see as our most useful contributions to the updating, revision and exploration of the consequences of the theory for various area of research. After an introductory chapter outlining the main tenets of theory and setting it within a broader philosophical and linguistic context, the book falls into three main parts. Part 1, Relevance and Meaning, is concerned with the relation between coding and inference in communication and the nature of the inference processes involved. Its central themes are the capacity of humans to entertain and communicate concepts which are not the encoded meaning of any public word, and the inadequacy of the traditional distinction between literal and figurative meaning. We defend the view that there is a continuum of cases between literal, loose and metaphorical uses of language, and that the interpretation of metaphorical uses involves no special principles or mechanisms beyond those required for the interpretation of ordinary literal utterances. We end this part with a new chapter on the relevance-theoretic account of irony and its relation to some alternative accounts. Relevance theorists were among the earliest defenders of the so-called linguistic underdeterminacy thesis (the claim that pragmatic processes contribute much more to explicit side of communication than was traditionally assumed), and Part 2, Explicit and Implicit Communication, explores some of the arguments for this approach. We start by surveying the various ways in which information can be conveyed by an utterance, and then look in more detail at the temporal and causal connotations sometimes carried by conjoined utterances, at approaches to the analysis of bridging reference, the semantics and pragmatics of nondeclarative utterances, and the contribution of metarepresentational processes to the interpretation of utterances in general, and to explicit content in particular. Part 3, Cross-disciplinary Themes, considers some of the broader implications of the theory. We present arguments for a modular approach to comprehension, report some

experiments designed to test the main tenets of the theory, and reassess current treatments of so-called scalar implicatures in both theoretical and experimental terms. The book ends with a discussion of the implications of relevance theory for the evolution of language. Preface CONTENTS INTRODUCTION 1. Pragmatics 2. Three approaches to pragmatics 3. Literalism and contextualism in semantics 4. Explicit and implicit communication 5. Lexical pragmatics: metaphor, approximation and narrowing 6. Procedural meaning: speech acts, presuppositions and indexicals 7. Conclusion PART 1: RELEVANCE AND MEANING 2. The mapping between the mental and the public lexicon 2. Three types of mapping 3. Inference and relevance 4. Relevance and meaning 5. Implications 3. Truthfulness and relevance 2. The case of tropes

3. The case of loose use 4. Relevance: theory 5. Relevance: illustration 6. The explicit communication of unencoded meanings 7. Rethinking explicit, literal and what is said 4. Rhetoric and relevance 1. A paradox and a dilemma 2. Relevance theory 3. Literalness, looseness and metaphor 4. Echoing and irony 5. The relevance of rhetoric 5. A deflationary account of metaphors 2. The function of language in communication 3. How relevance guides inferential comprehension 4. Meaning construction 5. The literal loose metaphorical continuum 6. Inferential steps 7. Strength of contextual implications, strength of implicatures 8. Poetic effects 6. Explaining irony 1. Traditional approaches to irony 2. Three puzzling features of irony 3. The echoic account of irony 4. Pretence accounts of irony 5. Hybrid attributive pretence accounts 6. Explaining the puzzling features of irony 7. Conclusion PART 2: EXPLICIT AND IMPLICIT COMMUNICATION 7. Linguistic form and relevance 2. Conveying and ostensively communicating 3. Linguistic and non-linguistic communication 4. Linguistic communication and encoding 5. Conceptual and non-conceptual encoding 6. Explicit and implicit conceptual encoding

7. Proposition expressed versus higher-level explicature 8. Constraints on explicatures and constraints on implicatures 9. Conclusion 8. Pragmatics and time 2. Temporal and causal connotations: implicatures or pragmatically determined aspects of what is said? 3. The sequencing problem and the maxim Be orderly 4. Understanding and relevance 5. The interval problem 6. The role of contextual assumptions 7. Reverse-causal interpretations 8. Conclusion 9. Recent approaches to bridging: Truth, coherence, relevance Deirdre Wilson and Tomoko Matsui 2. Pragmatic approaches to bridging 3. Relevance theory and bridging 4. Comparing coherence theory and relevance theory 5. Conclusion 10. Mood and the analysis of non-declarative sentences 1. Distinguishing mood and force 2. Characterising imperative mood 3. Explaining non-literal, non-serious cases 4. Characterising interrogative mood 5. Conclusion 11. Metarepresentation in linguistic communication Deirdre Wilson 2. Gricean pragmatics and mindreading 3. Relevance theory and communication 4. Relevance theory and linguistic metarepresentation 5. Conclusion PART 3: CROSS-DISCIPLINARY THEMES 12. Pragmatics, modularity and mindreading 2. Two approaches to communication 3. Two approaches to inferential communication 4. Relevance, cognition and communication 5. Relevance and pragmatics 6. Conclusion 13. Testing the cognitive and communicative principles of relevance

Jean-Baptiste Van der Henst and Dan Sperber 2. The basic tenets of relevance theory 3. Testing the Cognitive Principle of Relevance with relational reasoning tasks 4. Testing the Communicative Principle of Relevance with the Wason Selection Task 5. Testing the Communicative Principle of Relevance with a speech production task 6. Conclusion 14. The why and how of experimental pragmatics Ira Noveck and Dan Sperber 1. Methodological background: the limits of pragmatic intuitions as evidence 2. Theoretical background: scalar implicatures as Generalised Conversational Implicatures (GCIs) 3. Relevance theory s approach 4. Methodological considerations in experimental approaches to scalar inferences 5. Developmental studies 6. The time course of comprehension among adults 7. Conclusions 15. A pragmatic perspective on the evolution of language Dan Sperber and Gloria Origgi 2. Two models of communication 3. The evolution of language and the two models of communication 4. Conclusions Notes References Index