Focus Constructions in ASL: Evidence from Pseudoclefting and Doubling

Similar documents
Som and Optimality Theory

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

The Structure of Relative Clauses in Maay Maay By Elly Zimmer

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

Argument structure and theta roles

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Describing Motion Events in Adult L2 Spanish Narratives

Acquiring verb agreement in HKSL: Optional or obligatory?

Part I. Figuring out how English works

The optimal placement of up and ab A comparison 1

Korean ECM Constructions and Cyclic Linearization

Focusing bound pronouns

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Pseudo-Passives as Adjectival Passives

The presence of interpretable but ungrammatical sentences corresponds to mismatches between interpretive and productive parsing.

Common Core State Standards for English Language Arts

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

Inleiding Taalkunde. Docent: Paola Monachesi. Blok 4, 2001/ Syntax 2. 2 Phrases and constituent structure 2. 3 A minigrammar of Italian 3

5. UPPER INTERMEDIATE

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Long-distance wh-movement. Long distance wh-movement. Islands. Islands. Locality. NP Sea. NP Sea

1/20 idea. We ll spend an extra hour on 1/21. based on assigned readings. so you ll be ready to discuss them in class

Agree or Move? On Partial Control Anna Snarska, Adam Mickiewicz University

FOCUS MARKING IN GREEK: SYNTAX OR PHONOLOGY? Michalis Georgiafentis University of Athens

NAME: East Carolina University PSYC Developmental Psychology Dr. Eppler & Dr. Ironsmith

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Achievement Level Descriptors for American Literature and Composition

Derivational and Inflectional Morphemes in Pak-Pak Language

The subject of adjectives: Syntactic position and semantic interpretation

Arizona s English Language Arts Standards th Grade ARIZONA DEPARTMENT OF EDUCATION HIGH ACADEMIC STANDARDS FOR STUDENTS

Theoretical Syntax Winter Answers to practice problems

LNGT0101 Introduction to Linguistics

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

On the Notion Determiner

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF MINNESOTA BY. Kaitlin Rose Johnson

Words come in categories

SOME MINIMAL NOTES ON MINIMALISM *

To appear in The TESOL encyclopedia of ELT (Wiley-Blackwell) 1 RECASTING. Kazuya Saito. Birkbeck, University of London

Oakland Unified School District English/ Language Arts Course Syllabus

LIN 6520 Syntax 2 T 5-6, Th 6 CBD 234

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

LING 329 : MORPHOLOGY

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

Chapter 3: Semi-lexical categories. nor truly functional. As Corver and van Riemsdijk rightly point out, There is more

Discourse markers and grammaticalization

CEFR Overall Illustrative English Proficiency Scales

Oakland Unified School District English/ Language Arts Course Syllabus

Grade 11 Language Arts (2 Semester Course) CURRICULUM. Course Description ENGLISH 11 (2 Semester Course) Duration: 2 Semesters Prerequisite: None

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

Language acquisition: acquiring some aspects of syntax.

Second Language Acquisition of Complex Structures: The Case of English Restrictive Relative Clauses

Word Stress and Intonation: Introduction

The Bulgarian Reportative as a Conventional Implicature Chronos 10. Dimka Atanassov University of Pennsylvania

Tagged for Deletion: A Typological Approach to VP Ellipsis in Tag Questions

Listening and Speaking Skills of English Language of Adolescents of Government and Private Schools

Dissertation Summaries. The Acquisition of Aspect and Motion Verbs in the Native Language (Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, 2014)

Objectives. Chapter 2: The Representation of Knowledge. Expert Systems: Principles and Programming, Fourth Edition

Developing Grammar in Context

A comment on the topic of topic comment

PHILOSOPHY & CULTURE Syllabus

When a Complement PP Goes Missing: A Study on the Licensing Condition of Swiping

California Department of Education English Language Development Standards for Grade 8

teaching issues 4 Fact sheet Generic skills Context The nature of generic skills

PAGE(S) WHERE TAUGHT If sub mission ins not a book, cite appropriate location(s))

THEORY OF PLANNED BEHAVIOR MODEL IN ELECTRONIC LEARNING: A PILOT STUDY

linguist 752 UMass Amherst 8 February 2017

Lecturing Module

Surface Structure, Intonation, and Meaning in Spoken Language

How to analyze visual narratives: A tutorial in Visual Narrative Grammar

The Syntax of Coordinate Structure Complexes

AN INTRODUCTION (2 ND ED.) (LONDON, BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC PP. VI, 282)

L1 and L2 acquisition. Holger Diessel

The Acquisition of Person and Number Morphology Within the Verbal Domain in Early Greek

Derivational: Inflectional: In a fit of rage the soldiers attacked them both that week, but lost the fight.

Reading Grammar Section and Lesson Writing Chapter and Lesson Identify a purpose for reading W1-LO; W2- LO; W3- LO; W4- LO; W5-

CONSISTENCY OF TRAINING AND THE LEARNING EXPERIENCE

5 Minimalism and Optimality Theory

Maximizing Learning Through Course Alignment and Experience with Different Types of Knowledge

CONTENUTI DEL CORSO (presentazione di disciplina, argomenti, programma):

Construction Grammar. University of Jena.

Prosody-Driven Scrambling in Italian *

The Structure of Multiple Complements to V

Derivations (MP) and Evaluations (OT) *

Compositional Semantics

Control and Boundedness

Psychology and Language

Review in ICAME Journal, Volume 38, 2014, DOI: /icame

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

Intervention in Tough Constructions * Jeremy Hartman. Massachusetts Institute of Technology

The Inclusiveness Condition in Survive-minimalism

This Performance Standards include four major components. They are

Copyright and moral rights for this thesis are retained by the author

Linguistic Variation across Sports Category of Press Reportage from British Newspapers: a Diachronic Multidimensional Analysis

WHY SOLVE PROBLEMS? INTERVIEWING COLLEGE FACULTY ABOUT THE LEARNING AND TEACHING OF PROBLEM SOLVING

Transcription:

Volume 19 Issue 1 Proceedings of the 36th Annual Penn Linguistics Colloquium University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 1-28-2013 Focus Constructions in ASL: Evidence from Pseudoclefting and Doubling Elise Stickles University of California, Berkeley, elstickles@berkeley.edu Article 24 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. http://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl/vol19/iss1/24 For more information, please contact libraryrepository@pobox.upenn.edu.

Focus Constructions in ASL: Evidence from Pseudoclefting and Doubling Abstract This study investigates two types of clausal structures in American Sign Language (ASL), rhetorical whquestions and doubling constructions. Following work by Petronio (1993), I assume the stance that rhetorical wh-questions are pseudoclefts (wh-clefts). Unlike languages that use focus particles or relative clause-like structures, here ASL achieves the semantic properties of a cleft by moving the counterweight answer of the rhetorical question structure to [Spec,FP], and topicalizing the question wh-xp. This is similar to Abnerꞌs analysis of the it-clefting semantics of the rightward wh-r construction in ASL (2011). Both pseudoclefts and doubles have been identified as potential sites for focus; doubles are commonly assumed to have emphatic/ prosodic focus (Wilbur 1994, Nunes and Quadros 2006) and it has been previously argued that pseudoclefts have information focus (Lillo-Martin and Quadros 2004). However, as it stands current work under-specifies the exact nature of the differences in information structure, particularly in terms of the nature of the predicational pseudocleft (Sandler and Lillo-Martin 2006), which has been variously referred to as emphatic, prosodic, and information focus; or simply just focus. From this viewpoint I analyze the differences in information structure between the two clausal types as based on the diagnostics of Kiss (1998). I argue that based on Kiss s analysis of the distinguishing syntactic and pragmatic features between identificational and information focus, the pseudoclefting construction constitutes identificational focus, and the doubling construction constitutes emphatic information focus. This working paper is available in University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics: http://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl/ vol19/iss1/24

Focus Constructions in ASL: Evidence from Pseudoclefting and Doubling 1 Introduction Elise Stickles * Like other languages, information packaging in American Sign Language consists of two types of foregrounding: topicalization and focus. ASL is a topic-prominent language and, as such, allows for up to two topic slots Chomsky-adjoined at the head of an utterance (Liddell 1980 and Aarons 1994, in Sandler and Lillo-Martin 2006). While topicalization is used to foreground old information already established in discourse, focusing stresses information new to the discourse world. As demonstrated by Wilbur (1994), ASL has fixed stress, with the prosodic stress occurring at the end of the utterance (technically an Intonational Phrase). It may be followed by some elements, such as tag questions, but those are analyzed as adjoined and not under the scope of the main utterance. As it has been argued that focused elements must receive primary stress, Wilbur (1994) concludes that ASL obligatorily must have focus at the end of utterances. 1 The current literature on information structuring in ASL generally concurs with this conclusion. However, there exists some confusion as to the type of focus itself; Sandler and Lillo- Martin s (2006) review, for example, occasionally but not systematically refers to it as information focus, sometimes in comparison with contrastive focus. They also note that doubled constructions, as argued by Petronio (1993), in which a sign is repeated at the end of a sentence, constitute emphatic focus as there is prosodic stress on the doubled element; this reflects the analysis of doubles in Nunes and Quadros (2006). However, Sandler and Lillo-Martin (2006) acknowledge that this is not entirely equivalent to information focus, as it may not serve to introduce new information but rather emphasize a given point. Hence, they refer to it as prosodic or emphatic focus. Petronio analyzes doubles as having [+Focus] (i.e., primary focus) and [+F] features, arguing that the left double is focused and undergoes focus movement (1993). Following Kiss (1998), this paper will seek to analyze two basic types of focus constructions, pseudoclefting (also referred to as wh-clefting), and doubling, in order to clarify the distinctions hinted at in Sandler and Lillo-Martin (2006). Lillo-Martin and Quadros (2004) conclude that the pseudocleft constitutes information focus on the basis it provides new information. However, I hypothesize that pseudoclefting constructions constitute identificational focus, whereas doubled constructions constitute information focus. I will demonstrate that the choice of pseudoclefting or doubling by a speaker is motivated by the information structure to be conveyed. This will clarify claims in the current literature as to the type of focus entailed in each construction: Petronio s (1993) prosodic emphasis will be aligned with Wilbur s (1994) utterance-final focus prominence to reveal the information focus nature of doubles, and Wilbur s (1996) treatment of focus in pseudoclefts will be refined to specify identificational focus. 2 Pseudoclefting: Identificational Focus Diagnostics Wilbur (1996) addresses a common discursive construction in ASL, rhetorical questions. These are used to provide explanation or as illustrative narrative devices. For example: 2 * I would like to thank my main consultant, Savio Chan, for his grammaticality judgments and helpful comments; I-Hsuan Chen and Line Mikkelsen for their immensely useful suggestions and comments; and the PLC 36 attendees for interesting commentary and discussion. Any errors are my own. 1 See, for example, Büring and Gutierrez-Bravo (2001) for a discussion of focus prominence and similar utterance-final claims in Spanish. 2 Following convention, ASL glosses consist of a main glossing line, the English translation below, and a line above delineating the spread of any non-manual marker. The non-manual markers in this paper are as follows: br eyebrow raise; whq raised eyebrows, associated with wh-questions; n headshake, indicating negation; hn head nod. PRO indicates pronominals. Some examples have been edited to due to inconsistent glosses between sources. U. Penn Working Papers in Linguistics, Volume 19.1, 2013

208 ELISE STICKLES (1) br (Wilbur 1996:233) SUE KNOW WHAT, BILL THIEF NOT What Sue knows is that Bill is not a thief These sentences are usually translated as rhetorical questions, What does Sue know? That Bill is not a thief. However, Wilbur treats them as clefted constructions. She argues that pseudoclefting is the appropriate analysis because they meet the four criteria as laid out by Foley and Van Valin (1985). Assuming Wilbur s analysis, we can proceed to apply Kiss s (1998) diagnostics for identificational focus. According to Kiss, identificational (ID) focus in English is realized as a it-cleft constituent; English wh-clefting behaves similarly, making ASL pseudocleft constructions a prime target for ID focus. 3 Wilbur (1996) analyzes the focused element in the ASL pseudocleft as moving to [Spec,CP]; this analysis can be easily modified to parallel Kiss s in that it moves instead to [Spec,FP]. In that case, it is reasonable to predict that ASL will parallel English in that ID focus in ASL will also give rise to clefting. Kiss s analysis of it-clefting in English is as follows: (2) It was to John that I spoke. (41 in Kiss 1998:258) Figure 1: Analysis of (2). Note the focused element John moves to [Spec,FP] (Kiss 1998:258). Thus in pseudoclefts, the counterweight answer part of the cleft following the wh-clause should undergo movement to [Spec,FP], just as it does in Kiss s analysis of it-cleft movement. Wilbur s work inadvertently hints at the ID focus analysis, noting that the focus phrase must provide all, and only, the expected information (1996:212). The exhaustivity she touches on grounds the main diagnostics for ID focus. It differs from information (info) focus in the following regards: 1. ID is exhaustive. 2. Certain constituents (universal quantifiers, also-phrases, even-phrases) cannot be ID foci. 3. ID focus takes scope; info does not. 3 Abner (2011) similarly analyzes rightward ASL wh-constructions as it-clefts.

FOCUS CONSTRUCTIONS IN ASL 209 4. ID focus involves movement; info does not. 5. ID focus must involve a maximally projected XP. 2.1 Exhaustivity One function of ID focus is exhaustive identification; 4 it supplies the complete answer to the open proposition. For example (using modified English translations of Hungarian data): (3) Where did Mary go in the summer? (11 in Kiss 1998:249 250) a. Mary went to Italy [among other places]. b. It was Italy where Mary went. (3a) demonstrates information focus, as it is not exhaustive in its answer to the question. In contrast, (3b) provides a complete answer to the question; Italy is the only place traveled to in the summer. It would be infelicitous to follow up (3a) with: c. %No, Mary went to Spain, too. However, it is felicitous to respond to (3b) with (3c), as the exhaustivity of (3b) is being negated. This exhaustivity test can be applied to ASL pseudoclefts, as in (4): 5 (4) a. br MARY BUY WHAT, JACKET What Mary bought is a jacket. Here, a jacket answers the open proposition, What did Mary buy? It is felicitous to follow (4a) with (4b), as it negates the exhaustivity of (4a): b. n NO, MARY BUY BACKPACK TOO No, Mary also bought a backpack. In contrast, this exchange is infelicitous, because (5a) is not exhaustive: (5) a. MARY BUY JACKET b. % n NO, MARY BUY BACKPACK TOO No, Mary also bought a backpack. This test indicates that the pseudocleft as shown in (4a) is exhaustive while the regular construction of (5a) is not exhaustive. Thus, we have our first support for ID focus. 2.2 Movement In Kiss s analysis (Figure 1) of English it-clefts, the focused element moves to [Spec,FP]; this movement is a crucial aspect of ID focus. Whereas ID focus involves movement to a specifier position, info focus does not. Compare Kiss s analysis to that in Wilbur (1996), which provides an analysis of pseudoclefting in which the wh-clause moves leftward, in line with the leftward whmovement analysis of Petronio (1993). (6) br (103 in Wilbur 1996:246) PRO 1 DISLIKE WHAT, JOHN POSS TIE What I dislike is that John has a tie 4 Depending on the language, ID focus can be exhaustive, contrastive, or both (Kiss 1998:245). 5 All examples without citations are data I elicited from a native ASL signer.

210 ELISE STICKLES Wilbur analyzes (6) as consisting of a leftward movement of the wh-xp, PRO 1 DISLIKE WHAT, to [Spec,CP]: Figure 2: Wilbur s analysis of (6) (Figure 7.4, Wilbur 1996:247). Figure 3: Re-analysis of (6) with a rightward CP. In this structure we see that the wh-xp is clefted by moving leftward to a specifier position. Wh-phrases are traditionally analyzed as moving to [Spec,CP] in ASL, as shown here. Although Kiss places focused elements in a [Spec,FP] position, the movement of the subject-np posited here by Wilbur is analogous, and it would be straightforward to alter her analysis to include a focus projection. Following the analysis of rightward wh-movement developed by the ASL Linguistic Research Project at Boston University (Neidle et al. 2000), I take [CP,Spec] to be on the right and analyze (6) as above. Note in particular that the wh-phrase PRO 1 DISLIKE WHAT is generated in-situ at [Spec,TP], and a non-manual br marker appears at a C. This aligns with my prior analysis of whphrases (Stickles 2010); leftward wh-phrases do not undergo movement but rather are basegenerated and have +br agreement with the non-manual marker. Notably, the +br spread only appears over the wh-phrase and not the counterweight JOHN POSS TIE; this is due to the fact that obligatory +br spread only occurs within the CP and thus does not spread down to the second CP, where the subject NP originates. Both Wilbur s (1996) analysis and my own analysis of the pseudoclefting construction make it apparent that the focused element must undergo some form of movement. For Wilbur, the XP moves to [Spec,IP]; in my version, it moves to [Spec,FP], following Kiss. Regardless of the analysis favored, in both cases we find that the focused element moves to a specifier position; in my analysis it moves to [Spec,FP], and the head of the FP has CP as its complement. This aligns with Kiss s analysis of ID focus-associated movement. Here the focused phrase, JOHN POSS TIE, is moved out of the lower CP into the focused position at [Spec,FP], aligning with Kiss s analysis. In this approach, the wh-phrase moves to [Spec,TP] and agrees with the non-manual marker +br appearing at C. This explains the obligatory +br spread across the wh-phrase but not the answer phrase: the non-manual marker only spreads within the CP and not down to the second CP, where the subject-np originates. 2.2.1 Evidence for FP Notably, this analysis also provides evidence for existence of FP. English can be analyzed as having FP, or without, in which case focus is merely a feature located on C 0 as in (7).

FOCUS CONSTRUCTIONS IN ASL 211 (7) What I hate is asparagus. Figure 4: Analysis of (7) without FP. If we attempt to apply this analysis to the same construction in ASL, we produce the following analysis of (8): (8) br PRO 1 HATE WHAT, MEAT. What I hate is meat.

212 ELISE STICKLES Figure 5: Application of the analysis in Figure 4 to (8). This analysis of (8) is problematic for two main reasons. First, we note that the wh-word WHAT is produced at [Spec,CP]; this is not an issue in and of itself, since that is where wh-words often move to. However, in previous discussions of wh-formation in ASL (e.g., Neidle et al. 2000) leftward wh-phrases arise at [Spec,TP]. More troublesome, however, is the location of [Spec,CP] and C 0 itself. The first CP has [Spec,CP] on the right. In contrast, the second embedded CP must have it on the left, both for the generated wh-word and the focus marker [+F]. If the head of CP is rightward, it would not take scope over the utterance and ID focus would not occur as intended. Hence, an analysis lacking an FP is substantially inadequate. This suggests that a dedicated FP does exist. 2.3 Scope In ID focus, the focused element holds scope over other scope-taking elements. According to Kiss, the identificational focus occupies a scope position...it marks the sentence part following it and c- commanded by it as the scope of exhaustive identification (1998:254). (9) It is always Mary that everybody wants to dance with. (23 in Kiss 1998:254) In this case, the exhaustive identification of Mary (as opposed to other girls at the dance) takes scope over the universal quantifier. Compare this to the rhetorical question structure of (10): (10) br ALL BOY WANT DANCE WITH WHO?, MARY Who all the boys want to dance with is Mary. This has the same reading as in (9), where the exhaustive identification of Mary has scope over the universal quantifier in the question. Thus in pseudoclefts the focused counterweight takes scope over other scope-taking elements, in this case the universal quantifier. 2.4 Universal Quantifiers and Also-phrases According to Kiss, universals quantifiers, also-phrases, and even-phrases cannot be ID foci. However, unlike English pseudoclefts, universal quantifiers appear to be permissible in ASL pseudoclefts: (11) br MARY BUY WHAT, EVERY JACKET What Mary bought was every jacket. Although this appears problematic, consider the differences between English and ASL pseudoclefts; whereas English (12) is not grammatical, ASL (13) is. (12) *What I bought was everything/nothing. (13) br ME BUY WHAT, EVERYTHING/NOTHING What I bought was everything/nothing. The unacceptability of (12) is based on the idea that universal quantification cannot be specificational. Thus the semantics of the ASL pseudocleft are different from the typical pseudocleft in that they do allow for specificational universal quantification. Therefore, applying Kiss s test is not applicable here to the ASL pseudocleft, as it still maintains the specificational and exhaustive nature of ID focus. We can also note that also-phrases in English and ASL pseudoclefts are ungrammatical:

FOCUS CONSTRUCTIONS IN ASL 213 (14) *What Mary bought was also a jacket. (15) * br MARY BUY WHAT, ALSO JACKET What Mary bought was also a jacket. Hence, while universal quantification is not applicable, we can still apply the also-phrase diagnostic, as it would violate the exhaustive nature of ID focus, and provide another line of support for ID focus. 2.5 Maximal Projection The analysis in Section 2.2. also provides evidence for Kiss s projection diagnostic. Because Kiss places ID focus into [Spec,FP], it must be an XP, a maximally projected head. As seen previously, the focused element of JOHN POSS TIE in Figure 3 is analyzed as a subject-np moving to a specifier position. Thus we conclude that the focused element is an XP. 2.6 Interim Conclusion I have thus far established that pseudoclefting in ASL fulfills all of Kiss s requirements for ID focus. Thus at this point we can support the first of our claims, that pseudoclefting constructions involve identificational focus on their counterweight, answer phrase. Now we can move on to the second portion of our claims: that doubled constructions constitute information focus. 3 Doubling: Information Focus Diagnostics Doubled constructions can occur in a variety of formats, including wh-words, modals, verbs, quantifiers, and negatives (Petronio 1993). They are characterized by a variety of properties, including the fact that the double is an X 0, not an XP (Petronio, 1993). Petronio s analysis of the double as an X 0, not an XP, provides our first clue that doubled constructions do not have ID focus, and therefore should have info focus. Recall that ID focus is limited to appearing only in XPs. Petronio s study does not distinguish between different types of focus, but she does claim that the leftward double undergoes focus-movement, which similar to wh-movement; this would suggest that the doubles are potential targets for ID focus, since movement to an XP is a feature of ID focus. However, I will show that the doubles do not undergo movement; this supports my claim that they involve info focus. Furthermore, I will claim that it is the rightward double which receives primary focus, in line with Wilbur s (1994) argument that utterance-final words receive primary focus. The diagnostics for info focus essentially entail applying, and failing, the ID focus diagnostics. 3.1 Exhaustivity Whereas ID focused utterances should pass the exhaustivity diagnostic, info focus is not exhaustive. Consider (16): (16) hn (16d in Lillo-Martin and Quadros 2004:168) BABY CRY BABY The BABY is crying. This can be treated as answering the question, Who is crying? ; however, it doesn t exhaustively delineate all the potential criers, as reflected by the infelicity of a similar English exchange: (17) Who is crying? a. The BABY is crying. b. %No, the toddler is crying, too.

214 ELISE STICKLES The fact that (17b) is an infelicitous response to (17a), which is analogous to (16), demonstrates that the focus BABY is not exhaustive. Hence, we have our first line of support for the claim that doubled constructions have info focus. 3.2 Movement Petronio (1993) treats the left double as the primary of the two, receiving [+Focus], and its twin as having an additional [+F] feature. However, given as stated in Wilbur (1994) that utterance-final elements receive primary focus, I argue that the rightward twin is actually the primary focused element. Indeed, the second double often has greater prosodic emphasis (more exaggerated facial expression, larger range of motion in the sign s motion parameter) than the leftward double. This suggests the sentence-final double is, in fact, primary, and thus retains focal prominence. The importance of the distinction between left and right foci will become clear in considering Kiss s movement diagnostic. According to Petronio (1993), the leftward double must receive focus because it undergoes focus movement, similar to wh-movement: (18) whq (Petronio 1993:149) WHO WANT READ WHO Who wants to read? In Figure 6, the focus WHO moves leftward to [Spec,CP]. Petronio claims this shows that it is focused. However, according to Kiss, elements receiving information focus are not associated with focus movement. If instead we consider the rightward double as the site for primary focus, we find that under Petronio s analysis the doubled WHO does not undergo movement. Figure 6: Here the leftward double is primary and receives focus. (Petronio 1993:150). Figure 7: Reanalysis of (18), wherein both doubles arise in-situ. This contrasts with claims by Neidle et al. (2000), who analyze the rightward double as moving rightward to [Spec,CP]. In my own analysis (2010), neither the leftward nor rightward doubles undergo movement. The left is base-generated in-situ at [Spec,TP] and the rightward is basegenerated in C, as is illustrated in Figure 7 (above). Under this analysis, regardless of whether we consider the left or rightward double WHO, the focused element does not move. Thus, they cannot have ID focus, since ID focus is associated with focus-movement. 3.3 Scope Unlike with identificational focus, the scope of an info-focused element is independent of its status as info focus. For example, the only possible interpretation of (19) is one in which the universal

FOCUS CONSTRUCTIONS IN ASL 215 quantifier takes scope over the whole sentence (Kiss 1998:254). (19) Every boy wanted to dance with the beauty queen. (24b in Kiss 1998:254) (19) is not exhaustive, as it could be that although the boys all wanted to dance with the beauty queen, they also wanted to dance with perhaps the first and second runners-up. Thus, the focused element the beauty queen is not ID focus. Similarly, in (20), the universal quantifier EVERY takes scope over the whole sentence: (20) What does Ann want to read? hn EVERY BOOK ANN WANT READ WANT Ann wants to read EVERY book. As in (19), the universal quantifier takes scope over the entire utterance; similarly, (20) is not exhaustive, as it does not delineate everything Ann possibly wants to read (newspapers, magazines, etc). Hence, since EVERY is taking scope over the focused element WANT, WANT cannot be ID focus. Instead we conclude it has info focus. 3.4 Universal Quantifiers and Also-phrases Because the types of words allowed to appear in doubled constructions are already restricted for separate reasons, it is difficult to evaluate them using this diagnostic. Also-phrases are not permitted as doubles. However, we can apply the diagnostic to the universal quantifier EVERY: (21) hn PRO 1 EAT EVERY COOKIE EVERY I ate EVERY cookie. The fact that EVERY is permissible as a double is not entirely remarkable on its own, as we previously noted that EVERY is also permissible in the pseudoclefting construction. However, when we consider both that also-phrases are ungrammatical in the pseudoclefting construction and the universal quantifier is grammatical in the doubling, we can conclude that, to the extent we can apply the diagnostic, pseudoclefting passes the ID focus test and doubling fails it. Since universal quantifiers can have info focus, this suggests the double EVERY here has info focus. 3.5 Maximal Projection According to both my and Petronio s analyses in Figures 6 and 7, the rightward double is basegenerated in C 0. This conflicts with that of Neidle et al. (2000), who place it in a rightward [Spec,CP]. Thus the analyses by Petronio and myself both support the claim that the rightward double receives information focus and not ID focus, as ID focus must appear at the XP and thus cannot appear in a head C 0. 4 Conclusions As we have seen based on the application of the diagnostics laid out in Kiss (1998), the counterweight of pseudoclefting constructions in ASL receives identificational focus. Conversely, the rightward double in doubled constructions receives information focus. While both these constructions have been the subjects of considerable analysis in the past, neither has been previously identified as targets for specific types of focus. This presents a unified account that resolves contradictions in the existing literature, including Petronio s (1993) leftward-moving doubles; Neidle et al. s (2000) doubled rightward focus in [Spec,CP]; and Lillo-Martin and Quadro s (2004) leftward-moving information-focused pseudocleft. Thus, I have clarified the distinguishing features between the two constructions, and provided a motivation information packaging for use of one over the other. Use of the pseudocleft in

216 ELISE STICKLES ASL is generally taken to be a function of discourse, and use of the double is regarded as simply providing extra prosodic emphasis. However, it is now apparent that not only do both receive focus as claimed in the prior literature but they are particular targets for different types of foci. Additional work remains to be done in terms of investigating other clefting structures in ASL; for example, previously rightward wh-constructions such as (22) have been treated as structurally similar to doubles with the assumption that the leftward double is simply unrealized: (22) whq NAME WHAT What is your name? However, Abner (2011) argues that they function as clefting constructions similar to English itclefts, and identifies them as another potential focus site; thus it remains to be seen what syntactic and information structural differences lie between the different clefting types of ASL. References Abner, Natasha. 2011. WH-Words that go bump in the right. In Proceedings of the 28th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. M. Byram Washburn et al., 24 32. Somerville, Mass: Cascadilla Proceedings. Büring, Daniel, and Rodrigo Gutiérrez-Bravo. 2001. Focus-related constituent order variation without the NSR: A prosody-based crosslinguistic analysis. Syntax at Santa Cruz 3: 41 58. Foley, William, and Robert Van Valin. 1985. Information packaging in the clause. In Language Typology and Syntactic Description, ed. T. Shopen, 282 364. Cambridge, Mass: Cambridge University Press. Kiss, Katalin É. 1998. Identificational focus versus information focus. Language 74:245 273. Lillo-Martin, Diane, and Ronice Müller de Quadros. 2004. Focus constructions in American Sign Language and Língua de Sinais Brasileira. In Signs of the Time: Selected Papers from TISLR 2004, ed. J. Quer. International Studies on Sign Language and Communication of the Deaf 41:161 176. Neidle, Carol, Judy Kegl, Dawn MacLaughlin, Benjamin Bahan, and Robert G. Lee. 2000. The Syntax of American Sign Language: Functional Categories and Hierarchical Structure. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. Nunes, Jario, and Ronice Müller de Quadros. 2006. Duplication of wh-elements in Brazilian Sign Language. In Proceedings of The 35th Conference of the North East Linguistic Society, ed. L. Batemen and C. Ussery, 463 478. Amherst, Mass: GLSA UMass Amherst. Petronio, Karen M. 1993. Clause Structure in American Sign Language. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Washington. Sandler, Wendy, and Diane Lillo-Martin. 2006. Sign Language and Linguistic Universals. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. Stickles, Elise. 2010. Wh-Movement in ASL: Non-Manual Lexemes vs. Visual Feature Checking. Paper presented at Syntax Circle, UC Berkeley. Wilbur, Ronnie B. 1994. Foregrounding structures in American Sign Language. Journal of Pragmatics 22:647 672. Wilbur, Ronnie B. 1996. Evidence for the function and structure of wh-clefts in American Sign Language. In International Review of Sign Linguistics, eds. W. H. Edmondson and R. B. Wilbur, 209 256. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. University of California, Berkeley Department of Linguistics 1203 Dwinelle Hall #2650 Berkeley, CA 94720-2650 elstickles@berkeley.edu