Linguistic Background on Control and Raising

Similar documents
Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

Pseudo-Passives as Adjectival Passives

Compositional Semantics

Chapter 4: Valence & Agreement CSLI Publications

Control and Boundedness

Argument structure and theta roles

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

GERM 3040 GERMAN GRAMMAR AND COMPOSITION SPRING 2017

ELD CELDT 5 EDGE Level C Curriculum Guide LANGUAGE DEVELOPMENT VOCABULARY COMMON WRITING PROJECT. ToolKit

THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & SOCIAL STUDIES

Advanced Grammar in Use

Aspectual Classes of Verb Phrases

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

Words come in categories

1/20 idea. We ll spend an extra hour on 1/21. based on assigned readings. so you ll be ready to discuss them in class

Theoretical Syntax Winter Answers to practice problems

Hindi Aspectual Verb Complexes

Which verb classes and why? Research questions: Semantic Basis Hypothesis (SBH) What verb classes? Why the truth of the SBH matters

Today we examine the distribution of infinitival clauses, which can be

Writing a composition

The Discourse Anaphoric Properties of Connectives

Some Principles of Automated Natural Language Information Extraction

Chapter 3: Semi-lexical categories. nor truly functional. As Corver and van Riemsdijk rightly point out, There is more

A Grammar for Battle Management Language

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

University of Groningen. Verbs in spoken sentence processing de Goede, Dieuwke

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

The subject of adjectives: Syntactic position and semantic interpretation

CHILDREN S POSSESSIVE STRUCTURES: A CASE STUDY 1. Andrew Radford and Joseph Galasso, University of Essex

PAGE(S) WHERE TAUGHT If sub mission ins not a book, cite appropriate location(s))

Inleiding Taalkunde. Docent: Paola Monachesi. Blok 4, 2001/ Syntax 2. 2 Phrases and constituent structure 2. 3 A minigrammar of Italian 3

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

Switched Control and other 'uncontrolled' cases of obligatory control

cambridge occasional papers in linguistics Volume 8, Article 3: 41 55, 2015 ISSN

Linguistic Variation across Sports Category of Press Reportage from British Newspapers: a Diachronic Multidimensional Analysis

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

Structure-Preserving Extraction without Traces

Mercer County Schools

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

Parsing of part-of-speech tagged Assamese Texts

Informatics 2A: Language Complexity and the. Inf2A: Chomsky Hierarchy

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

Phenomena of gender attraction in Polish *

Reading Grammar Section and Lesson Writing Chapter and Lesson Identify a purpose for reading W1-LO; W2- LO; W3- LO; W4- LO; W5-

Intension, Attitude, and Tense Annotation in a High-Fidelity Semantic Representation

Objectives. Chapter 2: The Representation of Knowledge. Expert Systems: Principles and Programming, Fourth Edition

Senior Stenographer / Senior Typist Series (including equivalent Secretary titles)

Construction Grammar. University of Jena.

Derivational: Inflectional: In a fit of rage the soldiers attacked them both that week, but lost the fight.

Natural Language Processing. George Konidaris

LQVSumm: A Corpus of Linguistic Quality Violations in Multi-Document Summarization

ON THE SYNTAX AND SEMANTICS

EdIt: A Broad-Coverage Grammar Checker Using Pattern Grammar

California Department of Education English Language Development Standards for Grade 8

Author: Justyna Kowalczys Stowarzyszenie Angielski w Medycynie (PL) Feb 2015

Enhancing Unlexicalized Parsing Performance using a Wide Coverage Lexicon, Fuzzy Tag-set Mapping, and EM-HMM-based Lexical Probabilities

Target Language Preposition Selection an Experiment with Transformation-Based Learning and Aligned Bilingual Data

Campus Academic Resource Program An Object of a Preposition: A Prepositional Phrase: noun adjective

Korean ECM Constructions and Cyclic Linearization

LFG Semantics via Constraints

a) analyse sentences, so you know what s going on and how to use that information to help you find the answer.

On the Notion Determiner

Participate in expanded conversations and respond appropriately to a variety of conversational prompts

CORPUS ANALYSIS CORPUS ANALYSIS QUANTITATIVE ANALYSIS

Type-driven semantic interpretation and feature dependencies in R-LFG

Grammar Lesson Plan: Yes/No Questions with No Overt Auxiliary Verbs

Using dialogue context to improve parsing performance in dialogue systems

Rubric for Scoring English 1 Unit 1, Rhetorical Analysis

A First-Pass Approach for Evaluating Machine Translation Systems

Derivational and Inflectional Morphemes in Pak-Pak Language

Language acquisition: acquiring some aspects of syntax.

Lexical Categories and the Projection of Argument Structure

Probabilistic Latent Semantic Analysis

Emmaus Lutheran School English Language Arts Curriculum

Part III: Semantics. Notes on Natural Language Processing. Chia-Ping Chen

Beginners French FREN 101 University Studies Program. Course Outline

Chapter 1 The functional approach to language and the typological approach to grammar

Types and Lexical Semantics

Teacher: Mlle PERCHE Maeva High School: Lycée Charles Poncet, Cluses (74) Level: Seconde i.e year old students

15 The syntax of overmarking and kes in child Korean

Focusing bound pronouns

Text: envisionmath by Scott Foresman Addison Wesley. Course Description

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

Semantic Inference at the Lexical-Syntactic Level for Textual Entailment Recognition

Context Free Grammars. Many slides from Michael Collins

Unit 8 Pronoun References

A construction analysis of [be done X] in Canadian English

Tibor Kiss Reconstituting Grammar: Hagit Borer's Exoskeletal Syntax 1

What Structures Are Underlying Structures?

The Structure of Multiple Complements to V

The Internet as a Normative Corpus: Grammar Checking with a Search Engine

Language Acquisition by Identical vs. Fraternal SLI Twins * Karin Stromswold & Jay I. Rifkin

The building blocks of HPSG grammars. Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG) HPSG grammars from a linguistic perspective

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Transcription:

Linguistic Background on Control and Raising Carl Pollard The Ohio State University July 12, 2011 One of the central topics in syntactic theory since its beginnings has been the analysis of what traditional grammar referred to as understood subjects. That is: how should we account for the interpretation of (at least seemingly) subjectless verbal or predicative complements? As early as the 1960 s, it was realized that predicates 1 with such complements could be cross-classified on two dimensions: (a) subject vs. object control, and (2) equi vs. raising. Subject vs. Oject Control Intutively, to say that a verbal/predicative complement is controlled by the matrix subject (object) is to say that it is semantically interpreted as if it had a subject which is identical (in a sense which remains to be made precise) with the matrix subject (object). Predicates with such complements are called control predicates, and the matrix argument (subject or object) 2 on which the understood subject of the complement depends for its interpretation is called the controller. (1) Subject Control a. i. Kim tried/hoped/managed/aimed to be optimistic. ii. Kim promised (Sandy) to be optimistic. iii. Kim was eager/reluctant/willing/inclined to be optimistic. 1 Here and henceforth, we adopt the term (syntactic) predicate for any expression whose final result s semantic type is p. In our examples, we will mostly consider verbs (e.g. try, seem, persuade, promise, believe), but there are analogous examples where the matrix predicate is a predicative adjective (e.g. eager, likely) or preposition (e.g. under (an obligation), in (no condition)). 2 For certain predicates, the controller can be a nonpredicative PP complement (e.g. appeal to). 1

b. i. Kim tended/continued to be optimistic. ii. Kim seemed/appeared (to Sandy) to be optimistic. iii. Kim struck/impressed Sandy as (being) optimistic. iv. Kim was likely to be optimistic. (2) Object Control a. i. Kim persuaded Sandy to be optimistic. ii. Kim appealed to Sandy to be optimistic. b. i. Kim believed/knew/considered Sandy to be optimistic. ii. Circumstances prevented/prohibited Sandy from being optimistic. iii. Kim made/let/had/saw/heard Sandy mow the lawn. There are a number of diagnostics for distinguishing subject and object control. First, if the complement verb is transitive and has a reflexive (respectively, nonreflexive) pronoun as its object, then the complement object must (respectively, must not ) have the controller as its antecedent: (3) Subject Control with Pronoun Complement Objects a. i. John i tried//managed/aimed to shave himself i /*him i. ii. John i hoped/wanted/expected to shave himself i /*him i. iii. John i promised (Sandy) to shave himself i /*him i. iv. John i was eager/reluctant/willing/inclined to shave himself i /*him i. b. i. John i tended/continued shave himself i /*him i. ii. John i seemed/appeared (to Mary) to be shaving himself i /*him i. iii. John i struck/impressed Mary as (being) overly fond of himself i /*him i. iv. John i was likely to shave himself i /*him i. (4) Object Control with Pronoun Complement Objects a. i. Mary persuaded John i to shave himself i /*him i. ii. Mary appealed to John i to shave himself i /*him i. b. i. Mary believed/knew/considered John i to be overly fond of himself i /*him i.. ii. Circumstances prevented/prohibited John i from shaving himself i /*him i. 2

iii. Mary made/let/had/saw/heard John i shave himself i /*him i. Second, for many control predicates, there are alternative subcategorizations (i.e. different lexical entries for the same word ) with a sentential complement instead of a VP or predicative complement. In such cases, a sentence with a control predicate can be (nearly) paraphrased by a sentence with a sentential complement whose (complement) subject is identical with the controller of the control predicate: (5) Pronominal Subjects of Sentential Complements in Paraphrases of Sentences with Subject-Control Predicates a. i. John promised Mary/hoped/expected/ to win. ii. John i promised Mary/hoped/expected that he i would win. b. i. John appeared/was likely to be a vegan. ii. It appeared/was likely that John was a vegan (6) Pronominal Subjects of Sentential Complements in Paraphrases of Sentences with Object-Control Predicates a. i. Mary persuaded/convinced/advised John to be optimistic. ii. Mary persuaded/convinced/advised John i that he i should be optimistic. b. i. Mary saw John mow the lawn. ii. Mary saw that John was mowing the lawn. c. i. Mary believed/expected John to be optimistic. ii. Mary believed/expecetd that John was/would be optimistic. And third, many object-controlled predicates have passive counterparts (or pseudopassive ones, if the controller is a nonpredicative PP); but no subject-controlled predicates do, even if they have an NP object or a nonpredicative PP complement (this observation is known as Visser s Generalization): (7) Visser s Generalization a. i. Kim was persuaded to mow the lawn. ii. *Kim was promised to mow the lawn. b. i. Kim was appealed to to be reasonable. ii. *Kim was appeared to to be reasonable. c. i. Kim was viewed/described/regarded as inconsequential. ii. *Kim was impressed/struck as inconsequential. 3

Raising vs. Equi Crosscutting the distinction between subject and object control is another, orthogonal distinction referred to by syntacticians as raising vs. equi. The names originate with early transformational grammar: sentences with raising predicates were analyzed in terms of a raising transformation that literally raised the complement subject to the matrix subject or object position, while equi predicates were analyzed in terms of a different transformation, equi-np deletion, that deleted the subject of the complement if it was identical with the matrix subject or object (depending on the matrix predicate). In the examples (1) and (2) above, the (a) sentences have equi matrix predicates and the (b) sentences have equi matrix predicates. We have already mentioned some raising-to-subject (RTS) predicates, namely the auxiliaries (have,be, and modals) and noted how the determination of the type of the matrix subject is captured using schematic lexical entries each of which contains two occurrences of a category metavariable: (8) Auxiliaries as RTS Predicates λ s.have s; (A Psp) A Bse This analytic technique generalizes to nonauxiliary RTS predicates and to raising-to-object (RTO) predicates. By contrast, equi predicates are simply analyzed as taking NP or nonpredicative PP controllers, and complements that seek an NP subject that is underspecified for case ( PRO ). 3 This difference in the analyses explains why predicates like the ones in in (1b) and (2b), but not the ones in (1a) and (2a) can all have dummy controllers, as long as the controlled complement itself selects the same dummy subject. 4 However, there are many other differences between equi and raising predicates (some of which we will perhaps revisit in a problem set) that are not so easily explained. First, for some RTS predicates, there are alternative lexical 3 Semantically, the controlled complements of equi predicates can be analyzed as either properties (type e p), or through judicious use of lambdas as propositions that predicate a property of the individual denoted by the controller. Both approaches have their advocates. 4 The same holds true with idiom fragment in place of dummy : (1) a. The fix seemed/*tried to be in. b. The shit is likely/*eager to hit the fan. c. We believed/*persuaded Kim s goose to be cooked. 4

entries of the same word with just a sentential subject and no complement, or else a dummy it subject and a sentential complement: (9) a. i. Kim seems to be optimistic. ii. It seems that Kim is optimistic. b. i. Kim is unlikely to help. ii. That Kim will help is unlikely. iii. It is unlikely that Kim will help. But no subject equi lexemes have this property: (10) a. i. Kim tries to be optimistic. ii. *It tries that Kim is optimistic. iii. *That Kim is optimistic tries. b. i. Kim is eager to help. ii. *It is eager that Kim will help. iii. *That Kim will help is eager. Similarly, for some RTO predicates, but no object equi predicates, there are alternative lexical entries that take just an NP subject and a single sentential complement (but no NP object): (11) a. Kim believed/expected Sandy to have mowed the lawn. b. *Kim believed/expected Sandy that he would mow the lawn. c. Kim believed/expected that Sandy would mow the lawn. (12) a. Kim persuaded/convinced Sandy to mow the lawn. b. Kim persuaded/convinced Sandy that he should mow the lawn. c. *Kim persuaded/convinced that Sandy should mow the lawn. Second, raising predicates, but not equi predicates, preserve entailment under passivization of the complement verb if the controller is exchanged with the complement object: (13) a. Kim is likely to fire Sandy. b. Sandy is likely to be fired by Kim. [(a) and (b) are truth-conditionally equivalent.] 5

(14) a. Kim is eager to fire Sandy. b. Sandy is eager to be fired by Kim. [(a) and (b) are not truth-conditionally equivalent.] (15) a. Kim believed Chris to have fired Sandy. b. Kim believed Sandy to have been fired by Chris. [(a) and (b) are truth-conditionally equivalent.] (16) a. Kim persuaded Chris to fire Sandy. b. Kim persuaded Sandy to be fired by Chris. [(a) and (b) are not truth-conditionally equivalent.] And finally, raising predicates, but not equi predicates, exhibit certain ambiguities as to whether a quantified NP controller takes its semantic scope in the matrix or in the complement:: (17) a. A cop tended/was likely to stop there for doughnuts at 6:00 a.m. [Ambiguous.] b. A cop tried/was eager to stop there for doughnuts at 6:00 a.m. [Unambiguous.] (18) a. Kim expected a cop to come at 6:00 a.m. [Ambiguous.] b. Kim persuaded a cop to come by at 6:00 a.m. [Unambiguous.] 6