Subjective Attitudes and Counterstance Contingency

Similar documents
A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

The Bulgarian Reportative as a Conventional Implicature Chronos 10. Dimka Atanassov University of Pennsylvania

Focusing bound pronouns

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

The Strong Minimalist Thesis and Bounded Optimality

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

Going back to our roots: disciplinary approaches to pedagogy and pedagogic research

AGENDA LEARNING THEORIES LEARNING THEORIES. Advanced Learning Theories 2/22/2016

Language Acquisition Fall 2010/Winter Lexical Categories. Afra Alishahi, Heiner Drenhaus

1. Programme title and designation International Management N/A

Context-Sensitive Bidirectional OT: a New Approach to Russian Aspect

Author: Justyna Kowalczys Stowarzyszenie Angielski w Medycynie (PL) Feb 2015

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Module 12. Machine Learning. Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Types and Lexical Semantics

THE ANTINOMY OF THE VARIABLE: A TARSKIAN RESOLUTION Bryan Pickel and Brian Rabern University of Edinburgh

Arizona s English Language Arts Standards th Grade ARIZONA DEPARTMENT OF EDUCATION HIGH ACADEMIC STANDARDS FOR STUDENTS

PHILOSOPHY & CULTURE Syllabus

Interpreting Vague Utterances in Context

Linguistic Variation across Sports Category of Press Reportage from British Newspapers: a Diachronic Multidimensional Analysis

Control and Boundedness

Which verb classes and why? Research questions: Semantic Basis Hypothesis (SBH) What verb classes? Why the truth of the SBH matters

10.2. Behavior models

Adjectival Extremeness: Degree Modification and Contextually Restricted Scales

An Empirical and Computational Test of Linguistic Relativity

Higher education is becoming a major driver of economic competitiveness

Adjectival Extremeness: Degree Modification and Contextually Restricted Scales

Does Linguistic Communication Rest on Inference?

MASTER S THESIS GUIDE MASTER S PROGRAMME IN COMMUNICATION SCIENCE

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

Rubric for Scoring English 1 Unit 1, Rhetorical Analysis

Machine Learning and Development Policy

Parallel Evaluation in Stratal OT * Adam Baker University of Arizona

PH.D. IN COMPUTER SCIENCE PROGRAM (POST M.S.)

Dual Content Semantics, privative adjectives, and dynamic compositionality

AN INTRODUCTION (2 ND ED.) (LONDON, BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC PP. VI, 282)

The Effect of Written Corrective Feedback on the Accuracy of English Article Usage in L2 Writing

Segmented Discourse Representation Theory. Dynamic Semantics with Discourse Structure

Grade 11 Language Arts (2 Semester Course) CURRICULUM. Course Description ENGLISH 11 (2 Semester Course) Duration: 2 Semesters Prerequisite: None

GERM 3040 GERMAN GRAMMAR AND COMPOSITION SPRING 2017

Entrepreneurial Discovery and the Demmert/Klein Experiment: Additional Evidence from Germany

Written by: YULI AMRIA (RRA1B210085) ABSTRACT. Key words: ability, possessive pronouns, and possessive adjectives INTRODUCTION

Using dialogue context to improve parsing performance in dialogue systems

UCLA Issues in Applied Linguistics

Lecture 2: Quantifiers and Approximation

ReFresh: Retaining First Year Engineering Students and Retraining for Success

South Carolina English Language Arts

Document number: 2013/ Programs Committee 6/2014 (July) Agenda Item 42.0 Bachelor of Engineering with Honours in Software Engineering

BENCHMARK TREND COMPARISON REPORT:

"f TOPIC =T COMP COMP... OBJ

SCHEMA ACTIVATION IN MEMORY FOR PROSE 1. Michael A. R. Townsend State University of New York at Albany

AQUA: An Ontology-Driven Question Answering System

A Study of Successful Practices in the IB Program Continuum

Transitive meanings for intransitive verbs

Monitoring Metacognitive abilities in children: A comparison of children between the ages of 5 to 7 years and 8 to 11 years

Unit 3. Design Activity. Overview. Purpose. Profile

SHINE. Helping. Leaders. Reproduced with the permission of choice Magazine,

On-Line Data Analytics

Shared Mental Models

MOODY SUBJUNCTIVE IN ROMANIAN *

CEFR Overall Illustrative English Proficiency Scales

Lecture 9. The Semantic Typology of Indefinites

...WE CAN DO BETTER TIN-dag 2012, February 4, 2012

Accreditation in Europe. Zürcher Fachhochschule

arxiv: v1 [math.at] 10 Jan 2016

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 141 ( 2014 ) WCLTA Using Corpus Linguistics in the Development of Writing

Achievement Level Descriptors for American Literature and Composition

(Re)Formalizing the Imperative Sentence Type. David Medeiros,

Evaluation of a College Freshman Diversity Research Program

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

LEXICAL COHESION ANALYSIS OF THE ARTICLE WHAT IS A GOOD RESEARCH PROJECT? BY BRIAN PALTRIDGE A JOURNAL ARTICLE

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

Specification and Evaluation of Machine Translation Toy Systems - Criteria for laboratory assignments

Modality in Typological Perspective

What is Thinking (Cognition)?

The Good Judgment Project: A large scale test of different methods of combining expert predictions

A Comparative Study of Research Article Discussion Sections of Local and International Applied Linguistic Journals

Developing an Assessment Plan to Learn About Student Learning

Observing Teachers: The Mathematics Pedagogy of Quebec Francophone and Anglophone Teachers

Derivational and Inflectional Morphemes in Pak-Pak Language

Thesis-Proposal Outline/Template

MYCIN. The MYCIN Task

Seminar - Organic Computing

Probability and Statistics Curriculum Pacing Guide

Research as Design-Design as Research

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Digital Fabrication and Aunt Sarah: Enabling Quadratic Explorations via Technology. Michael L. Connell University of Houston - Downtown

Express, an International Journal of Multi Disciplinary Research ISSN: , Vol. 1, Issue 3, March 2014 Available at: journal.

Some Principles of Automated Natural Language Information Extraction

Interdisciplinary Research - Challenges and Opportunities for Actuarial Profession. Aldona Skučaitė, lecturer Vilnius university

Effective practices of peer mentors in an undergraduate writing intensive course

Accelerated Learning Online. Course Outline

Self Study Report Computer Science

An Interactive Intelligent Language Tutor Over The Internet

Phonological and Phonetic Representations: The Case of Neutralization

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

Transcription:

Subjective Attitudes and Counterstance Contingency CHRISTOPHER KENNEDY (University of Chicago) and MALTE WILLER (University of Chicago) Summary Across languages, SUBJECTIVE ATTITUDE VERBs (SAVs), such as English find, differ from ordinary doxastic attitude verbs (such as English believe) in that they require their complement to be subjective in a particular way. The goal of this paper is to develop a semantics for SAVs that predicts this fact but also captures the finer-grained differences between find-type SAVs and consider-type SAVs that make the former more restrictive than the latter. We propose that in terms of their core, at issue content, SAVs are just like believe in expressing a doxastic attitude towards the prejacent. They differ in that they introduce a presupposition that their prejacents are contingent relative to what we will call COUNTERSTANCES of the attitude holder s doxastic state: information states that differ only in decisions about how to resolve semantic underdetermination by the facts of the discourse situation. We provide a formal model for deriving counterstances from information states, the key idea being that an information state can be understood as the result of a decision procedure that involves application of multidimensional and evaluative choice functions, and thus provide a formal characterization of the two types of subjectivity that emerges in the variable acceptability of predicates under find and consider. The larger theoretical significance of our proposal is that it supports a characterization of subjective language as an essentially pragmatic, context-sensitive phenomenon, which does not correlate with semantic type (pace Sæbø) but derives from speakers recognition of the possibility of counterstance.

Abstract Background Sæbø (2009) examines SUBJECTIVE ATTITUDE VERBS, such as English find, with the goal of adjudicating between different formal accounts of the semantics of taste predicates, evaluative adjectives, and other expressions with subjective content [see also Stephenson 2007, Bouchard 2012, Fleisher 2013, Kennedy 2013, Bylinina forthcoming]. Find is notable because it requires its complement to be subjective in a particular way. Thus (1a) with the evaluative adjective fascinating is acceptable, but (1b) with vegetarian is not, even though this is an expression for which there may be inter-speaker variation as to which criteria are relevant for determining whether the predicate applies. (1) a. Kim finds Lee fascinating, because he is an expert on oysters. b. # Kim finds Lee vegetarian, because the only animals he eats are oysters. In this sense, find contrasts with the otherwise similar verb consider, which can be used with predicates like vegetarian (as well as fascinating): (2) a. Kim considers Lee fascinating, because he is an expert on oysters. b. Kim considers Lee vegetarian, because the only animals he eats are oysters. At the same time, consider is like find in rejecting fully objective predicates (Fleisher 2013): (3) a. # Kim finds the sum of two and two equal to four. b. # Kim considers the sum of two and two equal to four. Intuitively, the sentences in (1)-(3) all imply that it is somehow up to Kim whether the predicate in the complement can be truthfully applied to its argument (albeit in slightly different ways, as shown by the contrast between (1b) vs. (2b)), which accords with our understanding of the meaning and use of fascinating and vegetarian, but not equal to four. It is in this sense that both find and consider express subjective attitudes, and it is in this sense that they differ from a vanilla doxastic attitude verb like believe, which accepts any kind of predicate in its complement: (4) a. Kim believes that Lee is fascinating, because he is an expert on oysters. b. Kim believes that Lee is vegetarian, because the only animals he eats are oysters. c. Kim believes that the sum of two and two is equal to four. The goal of this paper is to develop a semantics for subjective attitude verbs (SAVs) that captures this intuitive characterization of their difference from plain doxastic attitude verbs, and also captures the finer-grained differences between find-type SAVs and consider-type SAVs that make the former more restrictive than the latter. Our analysis is inspired by the treatment of epistemic must in von Fintel and Gillies 2010. Von Fintel and Gillies are interested in explaining the intuition that a must-statement such as It must be raining is weaker that its non-modalized counterpart, while at the same time maintaining a strong semantics in which must p entails p. Their proposal is that in addition to its universal quantificational force, epistemic must carries with it an additional evidential component, such that an utterance of must p is appropriate only if the prejacent is known on the basis of indirect evidence or deduction, rather than on the basis of direct evidence. We claim that something along these lines is also right for find and consider. In terms of core, at-issue content, these verbs are just like believe in expressing a doxastic attitude towards the

prejacent. (Find-statements and consider-statements entail the corresponding believe-statements.) They differ in that they introduce a presupposition that their prejacents are contingent relative to what we will call COUNTERSTANCES of the attitude holder s doxastic state: information states that differ only in decisions about how to resolve underdetermination about arbitrary matters of linguistic practice. Our proposal We start with the familiar assumption that semantics assigns to sentences truthvalues at possible worlds and with respect to specific contextual parameters (standards of comparisons, modal bases, and the like), and we take it as a truism that the facts about a conversation are compatible with multiple ways of setting these parameters, and thus effectively underdetermine the truth-values of sentences in discourse. For the purposes of our analysis of subjective attitudes, two instantiations of such underdetermination are key. One is MULTIDIMENSIONALITY: given some set of facts, the conventions of language use remain consistent with multiple (possibly conflicting) criteria for assigning extension and anti-extension for some predicates. A second is EVALUATIV- ITY: even if the criteria for assigning extension and anti-extension are fixed, they may be consistent with multiple decisions about the assignment of extension and anti-extension for some predicates. In actual discourse interactions, participants partially resolve the contextual underdetermination in various ways, such as through explicit or implicit agreement about criteria (e.g., by deciding to exclude eating mollusks from the factors that would disqualify an individual from counting as vegetarian), by coordinating on evaluative judgments or tastes, and by other means. What is crucial for our purposes is the assumption that speakers are aware that these decisions, made in order to construct a common ground, are not based on objective facts of the world, but instead represent arbitrary decisions about linguistic practice. To capture the arbitrariness of the path to a (Stalnakerian) common ground and more generally, to any distinct belief state or information carrier we will embellish the familiar model of an information state as a set of possible worlds with a device for tracking salient decision points leading up to it. Specifically, we introduce a function κ which models the contingency of the stipulations involved in achieving an information state. κ takes an information state s and derives a partitioned set including s as well its counterstances: each such counterstance is a set of worlds that represents what the state would have been like given different contextually salient choices about how to resolve multidimensionality and evaluativity. Elements belonging to a single partition π in κpsq are those in which decisions about multidimensionality (but not evaluativity) are held constant. We have a formal model for deriving counterstances from information states, the key idea being that an information state can be understood as the result of a decision procedure that involves application of multidimensional and evaluative choice functions. Its counterstances are those states reachable by modulating the choice functions. On our view, a context determines a tuple xs,κy, where s is the common ground and κ is the mapping from an information carrier to a partition of its salient counterstances. We claim that both find and consider entail belief in the prejacent, and presuppose the contingency of the prejacent relative to counterstances of the subject s doxastic state which is just to say that belief in the prejacent is not based on objective information alone, but is rather based in a recognition that at least some alternative ways of resolving uncertainty in linguistic practice fail to preserve the truth of the belief. It is in this sense that find and consider denotes subjective attitudes.

Using the standard notation from Heim and Kratzer, we implement this analysis as follows, where DOX(W,X) maps an individualxto the worlds compatible with whatxbelieves atw: (5) a. vbelievew c,w λp xw,ty λx e DOXpw,xq Ď p b. vconsiderw c,w λp xw,ty λx e : Dπ P κ c pdoxpw,xqq Ds P π s.t.s Ę p. DOXpw,xq Ď p c. vfindw c,w λp xw,ty λx e : @π P κ c pdoxpw,xqq Ds P π s.t s Ę p. DOXpw,xq Ď p (5a) gives a standard denotation for believe. The denotation for consider in (5b) effectively introduces the presupposition that the prejacent is contingent relative to some counterstance of the attitude holder s doxastic state, which will be the case only if the prejacent includes expressions that introduce multidimensionality or evaluativity. The denotation for find in (5c) introduces the stronger presupposition that contingency persists even if we have resolved those aspects of indeterminacy that are subject to coordination (those stemming from MULTIDIMENSIONALITY, that is, matters of linguistic practice). This will be the case only if the prejacent introduces properly evaluative content. It follows from this analysis that if find p is acceptable in some context, so is consider p. We thus explain the contrast between (1b) (2b) as follows. (2b) is acceptable because differences in the criteria relevant for application of vegetarian across counterstances may impact the truth of the prejacent. (1b) presupposes that this impact persists even if we hold all relevant matters of linguistic practice constant, which will be the case only if the determination of the extension of vegetarian is sensitive to individual variation in experience. But this is not the case for a predicate whose applicability is determined by eating habits. It is, however, the case for a predicate whose applicability is determined by an experience of interest/engagement/curiosity/... like fascinating. An important feature of our analysis is that whether a predicate is counterstance contingent, and so whether it can be used to express the object of a subjective attitude, is crucially discourse sensitive, and does not correlate with semantic type as in Sæbø 2009 (a position that is criticized in Bouchard 2012). It may of course correlate with certain features of lexical semantics, such as the experiential semantics of taste predicates or the threshold semantics of vague predicates, but it may also depend entirely on practices of use, and it can change over the course of a conversation depending on how multidimensionality and evaluativity are resolved. Thus we see that in German, in which subjective find embeds full clauses, the sentence in (6) sounds acceptable in the immediate aftermath of a debate, when evaluativity remains unresolved, but it sounds odd once an exhaustive set of poll results have come in, effectively resolving evaluativity. (6) Ich finde, Obama hat die Debatte gewonnen. I find that Obama won the debate. Similarly, in English expressions that denote purely quantitative properties like heavy, dense and light can also take on qualitative meanings when used to describe objects that engage with sensory or aesthetic experience (like food, music or literature; see kennedy13 ). When embedded under consider, both the quantitative and qualitative senses are available: (7a) can be used express either Kim s judgment that the actual weight of the sauce is above a threshold for heavy (contingent relative to counterstances with different thresholds), or Kim s judgment that the sauce generates a feeling of heaviness in the stomach (contingent relative to couterstances with different evaluations). In contrast, only the qualitative sense is available for find in (7b).

(7) a. Kim considers the sauce heavy. b. Kim finds the sauce heavy. This difference follows from the different presuppositions of consider and find, but it does not entail a substantive semantic difference between the quantitative and qualitative uses of heavy; it is enough that our conventions for using the word are consistent with both multidimensional and evaluative uncertainty. Conclusion We have proposed an analysis of subjective attitude verbs as expressing counterstance contingent beliefs: beliefs that are based in a recognition that their truth is not preserved under alternative ways of resolving contextual underdetermination of the features relevant for fixing meaning. Our analysis is compatible with different formalizations of these features (e.g., relativist vs. contextualist vs. epistemicist), and indeed does not presume that they are homogenous. Indeed, if our analysis is correct, it suggests that subjectivity in language, as a general phenomenon, is not to be explained strictly in terms of any particular semantic parameter, implicit argument, or lexical underspecification, but rather emerges from language users awareness of counterstance: that the choices they make about how to resolve these features in the course of constructing a common ground could have been different. Additionally, it provides a formal characterization of the two types of subjectivity pointed at in work by Kennedy, Fleisher, Bylinina and others, which emerges in the variable acceptability of predicates under find and consider. References Bouchard, David-Ètienne. 2012. Long-Distance Degree Quantification and the Grammar of Subjectivity. Ph.D. thesis, McGill University. Bylinina, Lisa. Forthcoming. Judge-dependence in Degree Constructions. Journal of Semantics. von Fintel, Kai, and Anthony S. Gillies. 2010. Must...Stay...Strong. Natural Language Semantics 18(4): 351 383. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11050-010-9058-2. Fleisher, Nicholas. 2013. The Dynamics of Subjectivity. In Proceedings of SALT XXIII, ed. Todd Snider, 276 294. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications. Kennedy, Christopher. 2013. Two Sources of Subjectivity: Qualitative Assessment and Dimensional Uncertainty. Inquiry 56(2-3): 258 277. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2013.784483. Sæbø, Kjell Johan. 2009. Judgment Ascriptions. Linguistics and Philosophy 32(4): 327 352. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10988-009-9063-4. Stephenson, Tamina. 2007. Towards a Theory of Subjective Meaning. Ph.D. thesis, MIT.