Why semantics is the wastebasket. Matthijs Westera. Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam

Similar documents
The Bulgarian Reportative as a Conventional Implicature Chronos 10. Dimka Atanassov University of Pennsylvania

TAG QUESTIONS" Department of Language and Literature - University of Birmingham

Replies to Greco and Turner

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

Does Linguistic Communication Rest on Inference?

The Strong Minimalist Thesis and Bounded Optimality

Copyright Corwin 2015

PHILOSOPHY & CULTURE Syllabus

Introduction. 1. Evidence-informed teaching Prelude

Tutoring First-Year Writing Students at UNM

Gricean Communication and Transmission of Thoughts

MA Linguistics Language and Communication

Relevance Theory and the saying/implicating distinction *

A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF MINNESOTA BY. Kaitlin Rose Johnson

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

South Carolina English Language Arts

MASN: 1 How would you define pragmatics today? How is it different from traditional Greek rhetorics? What are its basic tenets?

Similar Triangles. Developed by: M. Fahy, J. O Keeffe, J. Cooper

Rubric for Scoring English 1 Unit 1, Rhetorical Analysis

5. UPPER INTERMEDIATE

Loughton School s curriculum evening. 28 th February 2017

The Foundations of Interpersonal Communication

1 3-5 = Subtraction - a binary operation

Part I. Figuring out how English works

Intensive Writing Class

MEASURING ORDINARY MEANING USING SURVEYS JP SEVILLA 3L and Levy Fellow George Mason University School of Law September 10, 2014

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

Observing Teachers: The Mathematics Pedagogy of Quebec Francophone and Anglophone Teachers

Arizona s English Language Arts Standards th Grade ARIZONA DEPARTMENT OF EDUCATION HIGH ACADEMIC STANDARDS FOR STUDENTS

Mandarin Lexical Tone Recognition: The Gating Paradigm

Multi-genre Writing Assignment

THE ALLEGORY OF THE CATS By David J. LeMaster

Assessment and Evaluation

The Task. A Guide for Tutors in the Rutgers Writing Centers Written and edited by Michael Goeller and Karen Kalteissen

Kelli Allen. Vicki Nieter. Jeanna Scheve. Foreword by Gregory J. Kaiser

How to analyze visual narratives: A tutorial in Visual Narrative Grammar

Section 7, Unit 4: Sample Student Book Activities for Teaching Listening

What is Research? A Reconstruction from 15 Snapshots. Charlie Van Loan

1. Answer the questions below on the Lesson Planning Response Document.

The Writing Process. The Academic Support Centre // September 2015

Critical Thinking in Everyday Life: 9 Strategies

LIMITED COMMON GROUND, UNLIMITED COMMUNICATIVE SUCCESS: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY INTO LINGUA RECEPTIVA USING ESTONIAN AND RUSSIAN

Teaching Task Rewrite. Teaching Task: Rewrite the Teaching Task: What is the theme of the poem Mother to Son?

CAN PICTORIAL REPRESENTATIONS SUPPORT PROPORTIONAL REASONING? THE CASE OF A MIXING PAINT PROBLEM

The Effect of Discourse Markers on the Speaking Production of EFL Students. Iman Moradimanesh

THE USE OF ENGLISH MOVIE IN TEACHING AUSTIN S ACT

Reinventing College Physics for Biologists: Explicating an Epistemological Curriculum

Book Review: Build Lean: Transforming construction using Lean Thinking by Adrian Terry & Stuart Smith

Managerial Decision Making

West s Paralegal Today The Legal Team at Work Third Edition

Critical Thinking in the Workplace. for City of Tallahassee Gabrielle K. Gabrielli, Ph.D.

Language Acquisition Chart

Achievement Level Descriptors for American Literature and Composition

ReFresh: Retaining First Year Engineering Students and Retraining for Success

1. Professional learning communities Prelude. 4.2 Introduction

Welcome to the Purdue OWL. Where do I begin? General Strategies. Personalizing Proofreading

Segmented Discourse Representation Theory. Dynamic Semantics with Discourse Structure

Abstractions and the Brain

TRUST AND RISK IN GAMES OF PARTIAL INFORMATION

Getting Started with Deliberate Practice

Lahore University of Management Sciences. FINN 321 Econometrics Fall Semester 2017

Scoring Notes for Secondary Social Studies CBAs (Grades 6 12)

MATH 205: Mathematics for K 8 Teachers: Number and Operations Western Kentucky University Spring 2017

Strategic discourse comprehension

Common Core State Standards for English Language Arts

Syllabus: Introduction to Philosophy

The Good Judgment Project: A large scale test of different methods of combining expert predictions

A Pumpkin Grows. Written by Linda D. Bullock and illustrated by Debby Fisher

CSC200: Lecture 4. Allan Borodin

Practice Examination IREB

Informatics 2A: Language Complexity and the. Inf2A: Chomsky Hierarchy

Individual Component Checklist L I S T E N I N G. for use with ONE task ENGLISH VERSION

Module 12. Machine Learning. Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Formative Assessment in Mathematics. Part 3: The Learner s Role

Testing for the Homeschooled High Schooler: SAT, ACT, AP, CLEP, PSAT, SAT II

Politics and Society Curriculum Specification

Toward Probabilistic Natural Logic for Syllogistic Reasoning

Chapter 4 - Fractions

Introduction to World Philosophy Syllabus Fall 2013 PHIL 2010 CRN: 89658

Software Maintenance

Lecture 1: Basic Concepts of Machine Learning

Procedural pragmatics and the study of discourse Louis de Saussure

Mental Models and the Meaning of Connectives: A Study on Children, Adolescents and Adults

The Master Question-Asker

Syllabus: PHI 2010, Introduction to Philosophy

The Algebra in the Arithmetic Finding analogous tasks and structures in arithmetic that can be used throughout algebra

Exploration. CS : Deep Reinforcement Learning Sergey Levine

Understanding the Relationship between Comprehension and Production

Specification and Evaluation of Machine Translation Toy Systems - Criteria for laboratory assignments

Edexcel GCSE. Statistics 1389 Paper 1H. June Mark Scheme. Statistics Edexcel GCSE

Introduction 1 MBTI Basics 2 Decision-Making Applications 44 How to Get the Most out of This Booklet 6

What the National Curriculum requires in reading at Y5 and Y6

Transitive meanings for intransitive verbs

Shared Mental Models

MASTER S THESIS GUIDE MASTER S PROGRAMME IN COMMUNICATION SCIENCE

Reviewed by Florina Erbeli

Writing Research Articles

Realization of Textual Cohesion and Coherence in Business Letters through Presupposition 1

Transcription:

A E Why semantics is the wastebasket Matthijs Westera Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Research Seminar in Logic and Language Tilburg, May 6th 2014

Outline Introduction Warming up: the implicature in (1) Semantics is the wastebasket (in the first sense) Grice on meaning Semantics and pragmatics Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket Pragmatics is not a wastebasket (in the second sense) Those flimsy conversational implicatures Defeasibility Cancellability Mixed experimental results Conclusion & outlook

1.1. Semantics and pragmatics Rough division of labour: Semantics: The study of sentence meaning, entailments, compositionality, etc. Pragmatics: The study of language use, context, implicatures, cooperativity, rationality, etc.

1.1. Semantics and pragmatics Rough division of labour: Semantics: The study of sentence meaning, entailments, compositionality, etc. Pragmatics: The study of language use, context, implicatures, cooperativity, rationality, etc. In a recommendation letter for a job in philosophy: (1) Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual.

1.1. Semantics and pragmatics Rough division of labour: Semantics: The study of sentence meaning, entailments, compositionality, etc. Pragmatics: The study of language use, context, implicatures, cooperativity, rationality, etc. In a recommendation letter for a job in philosophy: (1) Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. He has no philosophical qualities.

1.1. Semantics and pragmatics Rough division of labour: Semantics: The study of sentence meaning, entailments, compositionality, etc. Pragmatics: The study of language use, context, implicatures, cooperativity, rationality, etc. In a recommendation letter for a job in philosophy: (1) Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. He has no philosophical qualities. The inference explained as a conversational implicature: If the writer had known any virtue of Mr. X that actually mattered for the job, it would have been cooperative/rational to say so.

1.1. Semantics and pragmatics Rough division of labour: Semantics: The study of sentence meaning, entailments, compositionality, etc. Pragmatics: The study of language use, context, implicatures, cooperativity, rationality, etc. In a recommendation letter for a job in philosophy: (1) Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. He has no philosophical qualities. The inference explained as a conversational implicature: If the writer had known any virtue of Mr. X that actually mattered for the job, it would have been cooperative/rational to say so. (the standard recipe, but insufficient, cf. below)

1.2. The pragmatics wastebasket? Pragmatics is referred to as the wastebasket, in two senses: (i) what semantics cannot explain is left to pragmatics; (ii) conversational implicatures are flimsy, defeasible, weak, unreliable, cancelable, messy, unformalizable,...

1.2. The pragmatics wastebasket? Pragmatics is referred to as the wastebasket, in two senses: (i) what semantics cannot explain is left to pragmatics; (ii) conversational implicatures are flimsy, defeasible, weak, unreliable, cancelable, messy, unformalizable,... I will argue that, from a Gricean perspective: (i) ought to be (or can be) turned around; and (ii) rests upon several misconceptions. (some prevalent even among Griceans)

1.2. The pragmatics wastebasket? Pragmatics is referred to as the wastebasket, in two senses: (i) what semantics cannot explain is left to pragmatics; (ii) conversational implicatures are flimsy, defeasible, weak, unreliable, cancelable, messy, unformalizable,... I will argue that, from a Gricean perspective: (i) ought to be (or can be) turned around; and (ii) rests upon several misconceptions. (some prevalent even among Griceans) (Yes, I do pragmatics.)

Outline Introduction Warming up: the implicature in (1) Semantics is the wastebasket (in the first sense) Grice on meaning Semantics and pragmatics Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket Pragmatics is not a wastebasket (in the second sense) Those flimsy conversational implicatures Defeasibility Cancellability Mixed experimental results Conclusion & outlook

Outline Introduction Warming up: the implicature in (1) Semantics is the wastebasket (in the first sense) Grice on meaning Semantics and pragmatics Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket Pragmatics is not a wastebasket (in the second sense) Those flimsy conversational implicatures Defeasibility Cancellability Mixed experimental results Conclusion & outlook

2.1. Problems for the standard recipe (1) Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. He has no philosophical qualities.

2.1. Problems for the standard recipe (1) Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. He has no philosophical qualities. The standard explanation: Semantic theory: sentences denote pieces of information; Pragmatic theory: it is rational to utter a sentence denoting the strongest relevant piece of info you know to be true.

2.1. Problems for the standard recipe (1) Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. He has no philosophical qualities. The standard explanation: Semantic theory: sentences denote pieces of information; Pragmatic theory: it is rational to utter a sentence denoting the strongest relevant piece of info you know to be true. If the writer had known any virtue of Mr. X that actually mattered for the job, she should have said so.

2.1. Problems for the standard recipe (1) Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. He has no philosophical qualities. The standard explanation: Semantic theory: sentences denote pieces of information; Pragmatic theory: it is rational to utter a sentence denoting the strongest relevant piece of info you know to be true. If the writer had known any virtue of Mr. X that actually mattered for the job, she should have said so. Some problems: (Groenendijk & Stokhof, 1984) The obtained implicature is too weak: not-knowing, rather than knowing-that-not.

2.1. Problems for the standard recipe (1) Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. He has no philosophical qualities. The standard explanation: Semantic theory: sentences denote pieces of information; Pragmatic theory: it is rational to utter a sentence denoting the strongest relevant piece of info you know to be true. If the writer had known any virtue of Mr. X that actually mattered for the job, she should have said so. Some problems: (Groenendijk & Stokhof, 1984) The obtained implicature is too weak: not-knowing, rather than knowing-that-not. The account fails to tell (1) from (2): (2) Mr. X has excellent handwriting etc., or both that and he is a fantastic philosopher. He has no philosophical qualities.

2.2. Improved account: attentive pragmatics Intuitive solution: (Westera, 2013; & submitted) rationality is not only to assert all relevant, true information; but also to mention all relevant, possible information;

2.2. Improved account: attentive pragmatics Intuitive solution: (Westera, 2013; & submitted) rationality is not only to assert all relevant, true information; but also to mention all relevant, possible information; (2), but not (1), mentions that he might be a good phil.;

2.2. Improved account: attentive pragmatics Intuitive solution: (Westera, 2013; & submitted) rationality is not only to assert all relevant, true information; but also to mention all relevant, possible information; (2), but not (1), mentions that he might be a good phil.; the only excuse for not mentioning relevant information, is that you think it is false.

2.2. Improved account: attentive pragmatics Intuitive solution: (Westera, 2013; & submitted) rationality is not only to assert all relevant, true information; but also to mention all relevant, possible information; (2), but not (1), mentions that he might be a good phil.; the only excuse for not mentioning relevant information, is that you think it is false. Formal implementation: Richer semantic theory: informative content plus attentive content, i.e., the possibilities mentioned.

2.2. Improved account: attentive pragmatics Intuitive solution: (Westera, 2013; & submitted) rationality is not only to assert all relevant, true information; but also to mention all relevant, possible information; (2), but not (1), mentions that he might be a good phil.; the only excuse for not mentioning relevant information, is that you think it is false. Formal implementation: Richer semantic theory: informative content plus attentive content, i.e., the possibilities mentioned. Richer pragmatic theory: e.g.: draw attention to all relevant possibilities.

2.2. Improved account: attentive pragmatics Intuitive solution: (Westera, 2013; & submitted) rationality is not only to assert all relevant, true information; but also to mention all relevant, possible information; (2), but not (1), mentions that he might be a good phil.; the only excuse for not mentioning relevant information, is that you think it is false. Formal implementation: Richer semantic theory: informative content plus attentive content, i.e., the possibilities mentioned. Richer pragmatic theory: e.g.: draw attention to all relevant possibilities. This will make for a good illustration below.

Outline Introduction Warming up: the implicature in (1) Semantics is the wastebasket (in the first sense) Grice on meaning Semantics and pragmatics Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket Pragmatics is not a wastebasket (in the second sense) Those flimsy conversational implicatures Defeasibility Cancellability Mixed experimental results Conclusion & outlook

3.1. The empirical domain: language use...a more or less detailed study of the way we talk, in this or that region of discourse, is an indispensable foundation for much of the most fundamental kind of philosophizing. (Grice, 1986, p. 58)

3.1. The empirical domain: language use...a more or less detailed study of the way we talk, in this or that region of discourse, is an indispensable foundation for much of the most fundamental kind of philosophizing. (Grice, 1986, p. 58) This places Grice in: (cf. Neale, 1992) the ordinary language philosophy camp; and the meaning is use camp. Both of which, however, he also criticizes/refines.

3.1. The empirical domain: language use...a more or less detailed study of the way we talk, in this or that region of discourse, is an indispensable foundation for much of the most fundamental kind of philosophizing. (Grice, 1986, p. 58) This places Grice in: (cf. Neale, 1992) the ordinary language philosophy camp; and the meaning is use camp. Both of which, however, he also criticizes/refines....it is necessary to distinguish between a notion of meaning which is relativized to the users of words or expressions and one that is not so relativized;... of the two notions the unrelativized notion is posterior to, and has to be understood in terms of, the relativized notion;...what words mean is a matter of what people mean by them. (Grice, 1989, p. 340)

3.2. Speaker meaning, sentence meaning...what words mean is a matter of what people mean by them. (Grice, 1989, p. 340)

3.2. Speaker meaning, sentence meaning...what words mean is a matter of what people mean by them. (Grice, 1989, p. 340) A speaker means ψ p (by a sentence S) iff she intends: (i) that the hearer comes to think that the speaker ψ s p; (ii) that the hearer recognizes her intending (i); (iii) that (i) obtains in part due to (ii) obtaining. (and several refinements)

3.2. Speaker meaning, sentence meaning...what words mean is a matter of what people mean by them. (Grice, 1989, p. 340) A speaker means ψ p (by a sentence S) iff she intends: (i) that the hearer comes to think that the speaker ψ s p; (ii) that the hearer recognizes her intending (i); (iii) that (i) obtains in part due to (ii) obtaining. (and several refinements) A sentence S means p iff speakers tend to mean p by S.

3.2. Speaker meaning, sentence meaning...what words mean is a matter of what people mean by them. (Grice, 1989, p. 340) A speaker means ψ p (by a sentence S) iff she intends: (i) that the hearer comes to think that the speaker ψ s p; (ii) that the hearer recognizes her intending (i); (iii) that (i) obtains in part due to (ii) obtaining. (and several refinements) A sentence S means p iff speakers tend to mean p by S. Which speakers? In which circumstances?

3.3. Rationality and sentence meaning...the use of language is one among a range of forms of rational activity (Grice, 1989, p. 341)

3.3. Rationality and sentence meaning...the use of language is one among a range of forms of rational activity (Grice, 1989, p. 341) [T]o say what a word means in a language is to say what it is in general optimal for speakers of that language to do with that word, or what use they are to make of it; what particular intentions on particular occasions it is proper for them to have. Of course, there is no suggestion that they always have to have those intentions: it would merely be optimal, ceteris paribus, for them to have them. (Grice, 1989, p. 299)

3.3. Rationality and sentence meaning...the use of language is one among a range of forms of rational activity (Grice, 1989, p. 341) [T]o say what a word means in a language is to say what it is in general optimal for speakers of that language to do with that word, or what use they are to make of it; what particular intentions on particular occasions it is proper for them to have. Of course, there is no suggestion that they always have to have those intentions: it would merely be optimal, ceteris paribus, for them to have them. (Grice, 1989, p. 299) Thus, a theory of (conversational) rationality is presupposed by any theory of sentence meaning.

3.4. Rationality and speaker meaning

3.4. Rationality and speaker meaning To see what a speaker means: one must recognise her intention;

3.4. Rationality and speaker meaning To see what a speaker means: one must recognise her intention; this requires that her behaviour accords with her intentions;

3.4. Rationality and speaker meaning To see what a speaker means: one must recognise her intention; this requires that her behaviour accords with her intentions; hence, a speaker must presume that she is rational.

3.4. Rationality and speaker meaning To see what a speaker means: one must recognise her intention; this requires that her behaviour accords with her intentions; hence, a speaker must presume that she is rational. Certain things will follow from this presumption, perhaps even typically, that need not be part of sentence meaning:

3.4. Rationality and speaker meaning To see what a speaker means: one must recognise her intention; this requires that her behaviour accords with her intentions; hence, a speaker must presume that she is rational. Certain things will follow from this presumption, perhaps even typically, that need not be part of sentence meaning: Conversational implicature (CI) A part of what is meant, the intended recognition of which relies on the hearer s presumption of the speaker s rationality. (e.g., (1))

3.4. Rationality and speaker meaning To see what a speaker means: one must recognise her intention; this requires that her behaviour accords with her intentions; hence, a speaker must presume that she is rational. (This argument may be new; cf. Neale, 1992.) Certain things will follow from this presumption, perhaps even typically, that need not be part of sentence meaning: Conversational implicature (CI) A part of what is meant, the intended recognition of which relies on the hearer s presumption of the speaker s rationality. (e.g., (1))

3.4. Rationality and speaker meaning To see what a speaker means: one must recognise her intention; this requires that her behaviour accords with her intentions; hence, a speaker must presume that she is rational. (This argument may be new; cf. Neale, 1992.) Certain things will follow from this presumption, perhaps even typically, that need not be part of sentence meaning: Conversational implicature (CI) A part of what is meant, the intended recognition of which relies on the hearer s presumption of the speaker s rationality. (e.g., (1)) Thus, a theory of (conversational) rationality determines what a theory of sentence meaning must minimally account for.

3.5. Semantics and pragmatics In sum, a theory of (conversational) rationality: (i) is presupposed by any theory of sentence meaning; and (ii) determines what a theory of sentence meaning must minimally account for.

3.5. Semantics and pragmatics In sum, a theory of (conversational) rationality: (i) is presupposed by any theory of sentence meaning; and (ii) determines what a theory of sentence meaning must minimally account for. Recall our rough division of labour: Semantics: The study of sentence meaning, entailments, compositionality, etc. Pragmatics: The study of language use, context, implicatures, cooperativity, rationality, etc.

3.5. Semantics and pragmatics In sum, a pragmatic theory: (i) is presupposed by any theory of sentence meaning; and (ii) determines what a theory of sentence meaning must minimally account for. Recall our rough division of labour: Semantics: The study of sentence meaning, entailments, compositionality, etc. Pragmatics: The study of language use, context, implicatures, cooperativity, rationality, etc.

3.5. Semantics and pragmatics In sum, a pragmatic theory: (i) is presupposed by any semantic theory; and (ii) determines what a semantic theory must minimally account for. Recall our rough division of labour: Semantics: The study of sentence meaning, entailments, compositionality, etc. Pragmatics: The study of language use, context, implicatures, cooperativity, rationality, etc.

3.5. Semantics and pragmatics In sum, a pragmatic theory: (i) is presupposed by any semantic theory; and (ii) determines what a semantic theory must minimally account for. Recall our rough division of labour: Semantics: The study of sentence meaning, entailments, compositionality, etc. Pragmatics: The study of language use, context, implicatures, cooperativity, rationality, etc. Given (ii), semantics is the wastebasket (in the first sense): What pragmatics cannot explain is left to semantics.

3.6. What about attentive semantics and pragmatics? Recall, to deal with (1): Richer semantic theory: informative content plus attentive content, i.e., the possibilities mentioned. Richer pragmatic theory: e.g.: draw attention to all relevant possibilities.

3.6. What about attentive semantics and pragmatics? Recall, to deal with (1): Richer semantic theory: informative content plus attentive content, i.e., the possibilities mentioned. Richer pragmatic theory: e.g.: draw attention to all relevant possibilities. In light of the foregoing: Attentive semantics by itself doesn t predict anything;

3.6. What about attentive semantics and pragmatics? Recall, to deal with (1): Richer semantic theory: informative content plus attentive content, i.e., the possibilities mentioned. Richer pragmatic theory: e.g.: draw attention to all relevant possibilities. In light of the foregoing: Attentive semantics by itself doesn t predict anything;

3.6. What about attentive semantics and pragmatics? Recall, to deal with (1): Richer semantic theory: informative content plus attentive content, i.e., the possibilities mentioned. Richer pragmatic theory: e.g.: draw attention to all relevant possibilities. In light of the foregoing: Attentive semantics by itself doesn t predict anything; Attentive pragmatics, however, does double duty: it fixes what is meant by attentive content, i.e., what exactly is modeled by attentive semantics; and it simplifies the job left for semantics, by accounting for CI.

3.7. Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket This requires that we answer the following question: Why are conventions the way they are?

3.7. Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket This requires that we answer the following question: Why are conventions the way they are? Answering this requires a diachronic perspective: conventions must be useful and learnable;

3.7. Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket This requires that we answer the following question: Why are conventions the way they are? Answering this requires a diachronic perspective: conventions must be useful and learnable; compositionality would be beneficial;

3.7. Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket This requires that we answer the following question: Why are conventions the way they are? Answering this requires a diachronic perspective: conventions must be useful and learnable; compositionality would be beneficial; as would convexity of lexical concepts;

3.7. Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket This requires that we answer the following question: Why are conventions the way they are? Answering this requires a diachronic perspective: conventions must be useful and learnable; compositionality would be beneficial; as would convexity of lexical concepts; as would non-arbitrariness, e.g.: iconicity (e.g., onomatopoeia); naturalness (e.g., biological codes (Gussenhoven, 2004)).

3.7. Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket This requires that we answer the following question: Why are conventions the way they are? Answering this requires a diachronic perspective: conventions must be useful and learnable; compositionality would be beneficial; as would convexity of lexical concepts; as would non-arbitrariness, e.g.: iconicity (e.g., onomatopoeia); naturalness (e.g., biological codes (Gussenhoven, 2004)). This is the semanticist s toolbox

3.7. Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket This requires that we answer the following question: Why are conventions the way they are? Answering this requires a diachronic perspective: conventions must be useful and learnable; compositionality would be beneficial; as would convexity of lexical concepts; as would non-arbitrariness, e.g.: iconicity (e.g., onomatopoeia); naturalness (e.g., biological codes (Gussenhoven, 2004)). This is the semanticist s toolbox, given a pragmatic theory.

3.7. Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket This requires that we answer the following question: Why are conventions the way they are? Answering this requires a diachronic perspective: conventions must be useful and learnable; compositionality would be beneficial; as would convexity of lexical concepts; as would non-arbitrariness, e.g.: iconicity (e.g., onomatopoeia); naturalness (e.g., biological codes (Gussenhoven, 2004)). This is the semanticist s toolbox, given a pragmatic theory. (Work in progress: a compositional attentive semantics.)

Outline Introduction Warming up: the implicature in (1) Semantics is the wastebasket (in the first sense) Grice on meaning Semantics and pragmatics Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket Pragmatics is not a wastebasket (in the second sense) Those flimsy conversational implicatures Defeasibility Cancellability Mixed experimental results Conclusion & outlook

4.1. Those flimsy conversational implicatures Yet, implicatures in plain cases are well known to be flimsy and context-dependent. (Magri, 2011, p.13)

4.1. Those flimsy conversational implicatures Yet, implicatures in plain cases are well known to be flimsy and context-dependent. (Magri, 2011, p.13) But the effect is correspondingly weak: [it] produces cancelable implicatures rather than indefeasible truth conditional effects. (Beaver & Clark, 2008, p.41)

4.1. Those flimsy conversational implicatures Yet, implicatures in plain cases are well known to be flimsy and context-dependent. (Magri, 2011, p.13) But the effect is correspondingly weak: [it] produces cancelable implicatures rather than indefeasible truth conditional effects. (Beaver & Clark, 2008, p.41) [Conversational implicatures] are non-deductive. [...] Implicatures are [...] abductive inferences, or inferences to the best explanation [...] (Geurts, 2010, p.34)

4.1. Those flimsy conversational implicatures Yet, implicatures in plain cases are well known to be flimsy and context-dependent. (Magri, 2011, p.13) But the effect is correspondingly weak: [it] produces cancelable implicatures rather than indefeasible truth conditional effects. (Beaver & Clark, 2008, p.41) [Conversational implicatures] are non-deductive. [...] Implicatures are [...] abductive inferences, or inferences to the best explanation [...] (Geurts, 2010, p.34)...by characterizing a philosophically important distinction between the genuinely semantic and merely pragmatic implications of a statement, Grice clarified the relationship between classical logic and the semantics of natural language. (Neale, 1992, p.1)

4.2. Why implicatures are often considered weak Conversational implicature (CI) A part of what is meant, the intended recognition of which relies on the hearer s presumption of the speaker s rationality.

4.2. Why implicatures are often considered weak Conversational implicature (CI) A part of what is meant, the intended recognition of which relies on the hearer s presumption of the speaker s rationality. Why would CI be weaker than entailments? The presumption of rationality is defeasible; inferring intentions from behaviour is mere abduction.

4.2. Why implicatures are often considered weak Conversational implicature (CI) A part of what is meant, the intended recognition of which relies on the hearer s presumption of the speaker s rationality. Why would CI be weaker than entailments? The presumption of rationality is defeasible; inferring intentions from behaviour is mere abduction. Conversational implicatures are cancelable.

4.2. Why implicatures are often considered weak Conversational implicature (CI) A part of what is meant, the intended recognition of which relies on the hearer s presumption of the speaker s rationality. Why would CI be weaker than entailments? The presumption of rationality is defeasible; inferring intentions from behaviour is mere abduction. Conversational implicatures are cancelable. Experiments on implicatures show mixed results.

4.3. Conversational implicatures are not (really) defeasible CI may seem defeasible in, I think, three main ways: (i) it may be unclear what counts as rational ; (ii) the CI may depend on defeasible contextual cues; (iii) the rationality presumption may itself be given up.

4.3. Conversational implicatures are not (really) defeasible CI may seem defeasible in, I think, three main ways: (i) it may be unclear what counts as rational ; (ii) the CI may depend on defeasible contextual cues; (iii) the rationality presumption may itself be given up. @(i): True, but if that happens the CI simply isn t there, because: a rational speaker ensures that the CI is understood; after all, the CI is (part of) what is intended to be conveyed. Grice called this the CI s calculability.

4.3. Conversational implicatures are not (really) defeasible CI may seem defeasible in, I think, three main ways: (i) it may be unclear what counts as rational ; (ii) the CI may depend on defeasible contextual cues; (iii) the rationality presumption may itself be given up. @(i): True, but if that happens the CI simply isn t there, because: a rational speaker ensures that the CI is understood; after all, the CI is (part of) what is intended to be conveyed. Grice called this the CI s calculability. The presence of a conversational implicature must be capable of being worked out; for even if it can in fact be intuitively grasped, unless the intuition is replaceable by an argument, the implicature (if present at all) will not count as a conversational implicature; [...] (Grice, 1989, p.31)

4.3. Conversational implicatures are not (really) defeasible CI may seem defeasible in, I think, three main ways: (i) it may be unclear what counts as rational ; (ii) the CI may depend on defeasible contextual cues; (iii) the rationality presumption may itself be given up. @(i): True, but if that happens the CI simply isn t there, because: a rational speaker ensures that the CI is understood; after all, the CI is (part of) what is intended to be conveyed. Grice called this the CI s calculability.

4.3. Conversational implicatures are not (really) defeasible CI may seem defeasible in, I think, three main ways: (i) it may be unclear what counts as rational ; (ii) the CI may depend on defeasible contextual cues; (iii) the rationality presumption may itself be given up. @(i): True, but if that happens the CI simply isn t there, because: a rational speaker ensures that the CI is understood; after all, the CI is (part of) what is intended to be conveyed. Grice called this the CI s calculability. @(ii): Not if their defeasibility compromises the CI s calculability.

4.3. Conversational implicatures are not (really) defeasible CI may seem defeasible in, I think, three main ways: (i) it may be unclear what counts as rational ; (ii) the CI may depend on defeasible contextual cues; (iii) the rationality presumption may itself be given up. @(i): True, but if that happens the CI simply isn t there, because: a rational speaker ensures that the CI is understood; after all, the CI is (part of) what is intended to be conveyed. Grice called this the CI s calculability. @(ii): Not if their defeasibility compromises the CI s calculability. @(iii): This does not mean CI are defeasible, because: even if I do not in fact believe in a person s rationality, to see what she means I need but pretend that she is;

4.3. Conversational implicatures are not (really) defeasible CI may seem defeasible in, I think, three main ways: (i) it may be unclear what counts as rational ; (ii) the CI may depend on defeasible contextual cues; (iii) the rationality presumption may itself be given up. @(i): True, but if that happens the CI simply isn t there, because: a rational speaker ensures that the CI is understood; after all, the CI is (part of) what is intended to be conveyed. Grice called this the CI s calculability. @(ii): Not if their defeasibility compromises the CI s calculability. @(iii): This does not mean CI are defeasible, because: even if I do not in fact believe in a person s rationality, to see what she means I need but pretend that she is; This is why we can understand a known liar.

4.3. Conversational implicatures are not (really) defeasible CI may seem defeasible in, I think, three main ways: (i) it may be unclear what counts as rational ; (ii) the CI may depend on defeasible contextual cues; (iii) the rationality presumption may itself be given up. @(i): True, but if that happens the CI simply isn t there, because: a rational speaker ensures that the CI is understood; after all, the CI is (part of) what is intended to be conveyed. Grice called this the CI s calculability. @(ii): Not if their defeasibility compromises the CI s calculability. @(iii): This does not mean CI are defeasible, because: even if I do not in fact believe in a person s rationality, to see what she means I need but pretend that she is; This is why we can understand a known liar. (Besides, even entailments rely on the rationality presumption...)

4.4. Grice on cancellability Since, to assume the presence of a conversational implicature, we have to assume that at least the Cooperative Principle is being observed, and since it is possible to opt out of the observation of this principle, it follows that a conversational implicature can be cancelled in a particular case. [...]

4.4. Grice on cancellability Since, to assume the presence of a conversational implicature, we have to assume that at least the Cooperative Principle is being observed, and since it is possible to opt out of the observation of this principle, it follows that a conversational implicature can be cancelled in a particular case. [...] It may be explicitly canceled, by the addition of a clause that states or implies that the speaker has opted out, or it may be contextually cancelled, if the form of utterance that usually carries it is used in a context that makes it clear that the speaker is opting out. (p.57)

4.5. Cancelability does not imply weakness So, conversational implicature is cancelable in two ways: contextually: what is rational is context-dependent: (3) [In response to an inquiry about handwriting/punctuality:] Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual.

4.5. Cancelability does not imply weakness So, conversational implicature is cancelable in two ways: contextually: what is rational is context-dependent: (3) [In response to an inquiry about handwriting/punctuality:] Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. explicitly: a hearer may opt out from a maxim: (4) Starting with his {least relevant / non-academic} virtues, Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual.

4.5. Cancelability does not imply weakness So, conversational implicature is cancelable in two ways: contextually: what is rational is context-dependent: (3) [In response to an inquiry about handwriting/punctuality:] Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. explicitly: a hearer may opt out from a maxim: (4) Starting with his {least relevant / non-academic} virtues, Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. Cancelability implies that: the presence of CI correlates with what is rational in the given context (which may be explicitly announced/changed); but when present, the CI is as strong as can be. (a rational speaker will ensure this)

4.5. Cancelability does not imply weakness So, conversational implicature is cancelable in two ways: contextually: what is rational is context-dependent: (3) [In response to an inquiry about handwriting/punctuality:] Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. explicitly: a hearer may opt out from a maxim: (4) Starting with his {least relevant / non-academic} virtues, Mr. X has excellent handwriting and is always very punctual. Cancelability implies that: the presence of CI correlates with what is rational in the given context (which may be explicitly announced/changed); but when present, the CI is as strong as can be. (a rational speaker will ensure this) But (3)/(4) are not the textbook examples of cancelation...

4.6. Textbook examples of cancelation are misleading More typical examples (similar to Grice s...): (5) He is seeing a woman. (Oh,) but I didn t mean to imply that... (6) I saw some of the students. Indeed, I saw all.

4.6. Textbook examples of cancelation are misleading More typical examples (similar to Grice s...): (5) He is seeing a woman. (Oh,) but I didn t mean to imply that... (6) I saw some of the students. Indeed, I saw all. In both examples, there wasn t a CI to begin with: in (5), there was perhaps an unintended inference, not a CI; (and accidental entailments can be likewise corrected)

4.6. Textbook examples of cancelation are misleading More typical examples (similar to Grice s...): (5) He is seeing a woman. (Oh,) but I didn t mean to imply that... (6) I saw some of the students. Indeed, I saw all. In both examples, there wasn t a CI to begin with: in (5), there was perhaps an unintended inference, not a CI; (and accidental entailments can be likewise corrected) in (6), the CI would have arisen only with stress on some: (7) [In response to How many students did you see? ] I saw some of the students. # Indeed, I saw all.

4.6. Textbook examples of cancelation are misleading More typical examples (similar to Grice s...): (5) He is seeing a woman. (Oh,) but I didn t mean to imply that... (6) I saw some of the students. Indeed, I saw all. In both examples, there wasn t a CI to begin with: in (5), there was perhaps an unintended inference, not a CI; (and accidental entailments can be likewise corrected) in (6), the CI would have arisen only with stress on some: (7) [In response to How many students did you see? ] I saw some of the students. # Indeed, I saw all. Thus: When present, CI are as strong as can be. (6) only seems to work because it lacks context or intonation.

4.6. Textbook examples of cancelation are misleading More typical examples (similar to Grice s...): (5) He is seeing a woman. (Oh,) but I didn t mean to imply that... (6) I saw some of the students. Indeed, I saw all. In both examples, there wasn t a CI to begin with: in (5), there was perhaps an unintended inference, not a CI; (and accidental entailments can be likewise corrected) in (6), the CI would have arisen only with stress on some: (7) [In response to How many students did you see? ] I saw some of the students. # Indeed, I saw all. Thus: When present, CI are as strong as can be. (6) only seems to work because it lacks context or intonation. (cf. experiments)

4.7. Cancelability defeasibility Crucially, cancelability does not imply: A rational speaker can make a conversational implicature and then contradict it. (And none of the examples in the literature are of this kind.)

4.7. Cancelability defeasibility Crucially, cancelability does not imply: A rational speaker can make a conversational implicature and then contradict it. (And none of the examples in the literature are of this kind.) In fact, if CI s were contradictable it would have been puzzling: CIs are part of speaker meaning, hence intended; a rational speaker ought not reverse her intentions, except upon discovering a mistake.

4.7. Cancelability defeasibility Crucially, cancelability does not imply: A rational speaker can make a conversational implicature and then contradict it. (And none of the examples in the literature are of this kind.) In fact, if CI s were contradictable it would have been puzzling: CIs are part of speaker meaning, hence intended; a rational speaker ought not reverse her intentions, except upon discovering a mistake. (but mistaken entailments may be likewise corrected)

4.7. Cancelability defeasibility Crucially, cancelability does not imply: A rational speaker can make a conversational implicature and then contradict it. (And none of the examples in the literature are of this kind.) In fact, if CI s were contradictable it would have been puzzling: CIs are part of speaker meaning, hence intended; a rational speaker ought not reverse her intentions, except upon discovering a mistake. (but mistaken entailments may be likewise corrected) More directly: 1. CI follow from rationality presumption; 2. hence: if CI is false, speaker must be irrational.

4.8. Even entailments are cancelable Entailments enter speaker meaning only via the Maxim of Quality. But isn t this maxim stronger than the others?

4.8. Even entailments are cancelable Entailments enter speaker meaning only via the Maxim of Quality. But isn t this maxim stronger than the others? The maxims do not seem to be coordinate. The maxim of Quality [...] does not seem to be just one among a number of recipes for producing contributions; it seems rather to spell out the difference between something s being, and (strictly speaking) failing to be, any kind of contribution at all. False information is not an inferior kind of information; it just is not information. (Grice, 1989, p.371)

4.8. Even entailments are cancelable Entailments enter speaker meaning only via the Maxim of Quality. But isn t this maxim stronger than the others? The maxims do not seem to be coordinate. The maxim of Quality [...] does not seem to be just one among a number of recipes for producing contributions; it seems rather to spell out the difference between something s being, and (strictly speaking) failing to be, any kind of contribution at all. False information is not an inferior kind of information; it just is not information. (Grice, 1989, p.371) I disagree; a speaker can opt out and still make a contribution: (8) a. Okay, I ll just guess:... b. What I m about to say is false:...

4.8. Even entailments are cancelable Entailments enter speaker meaning only via the Maxim of Quality. But isn t this maxim stronger than the others? The maxims do not seem to be coordinate. The maxim of Quality [...] does not seem to be just one among a number of recipes for producing contributions; it seems rather to spell out the difference between something s being, and (strictly speaking) failing to be, any kind of contribution at all. False information is not an inferior kind of information; it just is not information. (Grice, 1989, p.371) I disagree; a speaker can opt out and still make a contribution: (8) a. Okay, I ll just guess:... b. What I m about to say is false:... (elsewhere I ve argued that a final rise can do the same.)

4.9. Mixed experimental results Consider again the role of context/intonation: (6) I saw some of the students. Indeed, I saw all. (7) [In response to Did you see all? ] I saw some of the students. # Indeed, I saw all.

4.9. Mixed experimental results Consider again the role of context/intonation: (6) I saw some of the students. Indeed, I saw all. (7) [In response to Did you see all? ] I saw some of the students. # Indeed, I saw all. Experiments (e.g., Van Tiel et al.) show mixed results, because: intonation is left implicit; question under discussion is left implicit;

4.9. Mixed experimental results Consider again the role of context/intonation: (6) I saw some of the students. Indeed, I saw all. (7) [In response to Did you see all? ] I saw some of the students. # Indeed, I saw all. Experiments (e.g., Van Tiel et al.) show mixed results, because: intonation is left implicit; question under discussion is left implicit; role of experimental task is ill-understood;... (e.g., Schwarz, 1996)

4.9. Mixed experimental results Consider again the role of context/intonation: (6) I saw some of the students. Indeed, I saw all. (7) [In response to Did you see all? ] I saw some of the students. # Indeed, I saw all. Experiments (e.g., Van Tiel et al.) show mixed results, because: intonation is left implicit; question under discussion is left implicit; role of experimental task is ill-understood;... (e.g., Schwarz, 1996) Participants may: (cf. Westera & Brasoveanu, 2014) fill in the gaps according to typical usage; and/or take the CI to be absent (because a rational speaker/experimenter would have been more clear).

4.9. Mixed experimental results Consider again the role of context/intonation: (6) I saw some of the students. Indeed, I saw all. (7) [In response to Did you see all? ] I saw some of the students. # Indeed, I saw all. Experiments (e.g., Van Tiel et al.) show mixed results, because: intonation is left implicit; question under discussion is left implicit; role of experimental task is ill-understood;... (e.g., Schwarz, 1996) Participants may: (cf. Westera & Brasoveanu, 2014) fill in the gaps according to typical usage; and/or take the CI to be absent (because a rational speaker/experimenter would have been more clear). This explains the apparent weakness of CI in experiments.

Outline Introduction Warming up: the implicature in (1) Semantics is the wastebasket (in the first sense) Grice on meaning Semantics and pragmatics Bringing order into the semantics wastebasket Pragmatics is not a wastebasket (in the second sense) Those flimsy conversational implicatures Defeasibility Cancellability Mixed experimental results Conclusion & outlook

5.1. Conclusion Semantics is the wastebasket, in the sense that: what it must minimally account for is determined by a pragmatic theory

5.1. Conclusion Semantics is the wastebasket, in the sense that: what it must minimally account for is determined by a pragmatic theory...which also fixes what the semantic objects mean.

5.1. Conclusion Semantics is the wastebasket, in the sense that: what it must minimally account for is determined by a pragmatic theory...which also fixes what the semantic objects mean. Pragmatics is not a wastebasket, in that CI are: not really defeasible (and no more so than entailments); only cancelable (but so are entailments).

5.1. Conclusion Semantics is the wastebasket, in the sense that: what it must minimally account for is determined by a pragmatic theory...which also fixes what the semantic objects mean. Pragmatics is not a wastebasket, in that CI are: not really defeasible (and no more so than entailments); only cancelable (but so are entailments). Cancelability of CIs does not imply weakness, but: systematic context-dependence; the systematicity is governed by rationality; studying this is the goal of pragmatics.

5.2. Outlook: my dissertation (due date October 2014) Argue for the following methodology: 1. take your favourite linguistic puzzle;

5.2. Outlook: my dissertation (due date October 2014) Argue for the following methodology: 1. take your favourite linguistic puzzle; 2. strip off everything that can be explained pragmatically; (and this can be done in a formal, rigorous way)

5.2. Outlook: my dissertation (due date October 2014) Argue for the following methodology: 1. take your favourite linguistic puzzle; 2. strip off everything that can be explained pragmatically; (and this can be done in a formal, rigorous way) 3. reduce the leftover semantic object via diachronic considerations, e.g., compositionality or natural meaning.

5.2. Outlook: my dissertation (due date October 2014) Argue for the following methodology: 1. take your favourite linguistic puzzle; 2. strip off everything that can be explained pragmatically; (and this can be done in a formal, rigorous way) 3. reduce the leftover semantic object via diachronic considerations, e.g., compositionality or natural meaning. And illustrate this in a number of cases: exhaustivity implicatures (e.g., (1)); intonational meaning: focus, contrastive topic, final contours; questions, yes and no ; Maybe: conditionals, presuppositions.

A E Thank you!