Greek Subjunctive Marker na: Temporal Anchoring in the DP Domain

Similar documents
Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

The Acquisition of Person and Number Morphology Within the Verbal Domain in Early Greek

Theoretical Syntax Winter Answers to practice problems

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

A non-finite period in early Cypriot Greek?

SOME MINIMAL NOTES ON MINIMALISM *

Agree or Move? On Partial Control Anna Snarska, Adam Mickiewicz University

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

The Structure of Relative Clauses in Maay Maay By Elly Zimmer

Second Language Acquisition of Complex Structures: The Case of English Restrictive Relative Clauses

California Department of Education English Language Development Standards for Grade 8

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

The presence of interpretable but ungrammatical sentences corresponds to mismatches between interpretive and productive parsing.

FOCUS MARKING IN GREEK: SYNTAX OR PHONOLOGY? Michalis Georgiafentis University of Athens

Aspectual Classes of Verb Phrases

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Long-distance wh-movement. Long distance wh-movement. Islands. Islands. Locality. NP Sea. NP Sea

ELD CELDT 5 EDGE Level C Curriculum Guide LANGUAGE DEVELOPMENT VOCABULARY COMMON WRITING PROJECT. ToolKit

Som and Optimality Theory

Today we examine the distribution of infinitival clauses, which can be

Control and Boundedness

Chapter 3: Semi-lexical categories. nor truly functional. As Corver and van Riemsdijk rightly point out, There is more

Derivations (MP) and Evaluations (OT) *

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

Dissertation Summaries. The Acquisition of Aspect and Motion Verbs in the Native Language (Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, 2014)

Heads and history NIGEL VINCENT & KERSTI BÖRJARS The University of Manchester

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

Korean ECM Constructions and Cyclic Linearization

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

GERM 3040 GERMAN GRAMMAR AND COMPOSITION SPRING 2017

THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & SOCIAL STUDIES

Argument structure and theta roles

Inleiding Taalkunde. Docent: Paola Monachesi. Blok 4, 2001/ Syntax 2. 2 Phrases and constituent structure 2. 3 A minigrammar of Italian 3

Derivational and Inflectional Morphemes in Pak-Pak Language

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

Opportunities for Writing Title Key Stage 1 Key Stage 2 Narrative

Tibor Kiss Reconstituting Grammar: Hagit Borer's Exoskeletal Syntax 1

cambridge occasional papers in linguistics Volume 8, Article 3: 41 55, 2015 ISSN

Course Outline for Honors Spanish II Mrs. Sharon Koller

Linguistic Variation across Sports Category of Press Reportage from British Newspapers: a Diachronic Multidimensional Analysis

Subject: Opening the American West. What are you teaching? Explorations of Lewis and Clark

Writing a composition

ENGBG1 ENGBL1 Campus Linguistics. Meeting 2. Chapter 7 (Morphology) and chapter 9 (Syntax) Pia Sundqvist

The Acquisition of English Grammatical Morphemes: A Case of Iranian EFL Learners

Discourse markers and grammaticalization

(Re)Formalizing the Imperative Sentence Type. David Medeiros,

The optimal placement of up and ab A comparison 1

MOODY SUBJUNCTIVE IN ROMANIAN *

What the National Curriculum requires in reading at Y5 and Y6

National University of Singapore Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences Centre for Language Studies Academic Year 2014/2015 Semester 2

Hindi Aspectual Verb Complexes

Taught Throughout the Year Foundational Skills Reading Writing Language RF.1.2 Demonstrate understanding of spoken words,

CAAP. Content Analysis Report. Sample College. Institution Code: 9011 Institution Type: 4-Year Subgroup: none Test Date: Spring 2011

Derivational: Inflectional: In a fit of rage the soldiers attacked them both that week, but lost the fight.

Lecture 9. The Semantic Typology of Indefinites

Universität Duisburg-Essen

A comment on the topic of topic comment

Age Effects on Syntactic Control in. Second Language Learning

Advanced Grammar in Use

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

PAGE(S) WHERE TAUGHT If sub mission ins not a book, cite appropriate location(s))

The Strong Minimalist Thesis and Bounded Optimality

Words come in categories

Focusing bound pronouns

Lower and Upper Secondary

Segmented Discourse Representation Theory. Dynamic Semantics with Discourse Structure

Tagged for Deletion: A Typological Approach to VP Ellipsis in Tag Questions

Hindi-Urdu Phrase Structure Annotation

Intension, Attitude, and Tense Annotation in a High-Fidelity Semantic Representation

Linguistic Inquiry, Volume 35, Number 1, Winter 2004, pp (Article)

Adjectives tell you more about a noun (for example: the red dress ).

Grammars & Parsing, Part 1:

The subjunctive conundrum in English 1

Document number: 2013/ Programs Committee 6/2014 (July) Agenda Item 42.0 Bachelor of Engineering with Honours in Software Engineering

TABE 9&10. Revised 8/2013- with reference to College and Career Readiness Standards

Student Services Job Family FY18 General

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Written by: YULI AMRIA (RRA1B210085) ABSTRACT. Key words: ability, possessive pronouns, and possessive adjectives INTRODUCTION

15 The syntax of overmarking and kes in child Korean

Morphosyntactic and Referential Cues to the Identification of Generic Statements

THE SHORT ANSWER: IMPLICATIONS FOR DIRECT COMPOSITIONALITY (AND VICE VERSA) Pauline Jacobson. Brown University

Citation for published version (APA): Veenstra, M. J. A. (1998). Formalizing the minimalist program Groningen: s.n.

Loughton School s curriculum evening. 28 th February 2017

Developing a TT-MCTAG for German with an RCG-based Parser

The Effect of Discourse Markers on the Speaking Production of EFL Students. Iman Moradimanesh

Cross-linguistic aspects in child L2 acquisition

Improved Effects of Word-Retrieval Treatments Subsequent to Addition of the Orthographic Form

Developing Grammar in Context

Language Acquisition Fall 2010/Winter Lexical Categories. Afra Alishahi, Heiner Drenhaus

Progressive Aspect in Nigerian English

Update on Soar-based language processing

linguist 752 UMass Amherst 8 February 2017

STA 225: Introductory Statistics (CT)

LNGT0101 Introduction to Linguistics

The Effect of Extensive Reading on Developing the Grammatical. Accuracy of the EFL Freshmen at Al Al-Bayt University

Intensive English Program Southwest College

Transcription:

ELENI STARAKI University of Chicago estar@uchicago.edu ABSTRACT. The goal of this paper 1 is to propose an account for those cases where the na marker is prohibited although expected according to the semantics of the verb. This shows that na marker and other markers of the same category are not always crucial for the anchoring of the perfective non-past (PNP) dependent verb form in plain Free Relative (FR) structures. Finally it shows it is possible for time reference to come from other domains in the structure besides the CP domain 1 Necessary background Before we present an analysis 2, it is necessary to provide some necessary background. The verb system in Greek employs three main morphological distinctions regarding the mood, the tense and the aspect in a binary mode, as follows: (1) Mood distinction: ± imperative (2) Tense distinction: ± past (3) Aspect distinction: ± perfective According to this distinction, we can have the following aspectual classes, for example. Example (a) is the imperfective non-past, (b) is the imperfective past, (c) is the perfective past, and (d) is the perfective non-past: (4) a. Milao b. Milusa speak.1sg was speaking.1sg I speak. I was speaking. c. Milisa d. Miliso Spoke.1sg speak.1sg I spoke. I speak. 1 I would like to thank Anastasia Giannakidou, Jason Merchant, my colleagues in the Research Seminar (Winter Quarter, 2007) and the audience of my presentation at the 2 nd Oxford Postgraduate Conference of Linguistics (LingO 2007) for their useful comments and criticism. Of course, all remaining errors are mine. 2 An extended version of this paper can be obtained by emailing the author. 220

The case that will engage us is (d), namely, perfective non-past (PNP). While all other verb forms can also occur alone in the structure, PNP has to combine with one of the markers of mood or tense that Greek employs. This set of markers includes na (subjunctive), an (conditional), as (optative) and tha (future). I will focus on na (subjunctive) and its conflict with plain Free Relative pronouns in (5). 2 Problems with the previous analyses (5) O-pjos (*na) milisi tha fiji The-who.interrog SUBJ 3 speak.3sg.pnp fut go.3sg.pnp Whoever speaks will go out. Previous analyses seem to make the wrong prediction regarding the obligatory presence of the marker. If the marker is obligatory in the structure so it can denote the mood or contribute the utterance time, then why do we have an ungrammatical sentence in (5)? The example in (5) raises the following questions: What exactly does the PNP need and what exactly does the na marker provide to the PNP? What is the locus of the conflict between the plain FR and the na marker? Why the marker na is impossible in the structures with plain FR? My proposal before we move in the main analysis is that the DP domain of the plain FR can also provide the temporal anchoring of the PNP dependent verb form. CP is not the only domain in the sentence providing this. 3 The analysis Giannakidou (2007) argues that the PNP in Greek is a dependent verb form. This means that the verbal dependent introduces an open interval, which always needs a reference time to anchor its left boundary. Otherwise, we have ambiguous interpretation between the present and a future time. The left open boundary needs to be anchored by an antecedent. Particles like na (subjunctive), an (conditional), as (optative) and tha (future) provide this open interval. These particles introduce n time parameter (or, utterance time) independently since the PNP cannot introduce it. The utterance time then serves to anchor the left boundary of PNP, thus yielding a future time reading. For example: 3 SUBJ = subjunctive 221

(6) *Milisi i Maria Speak.3sg.PNP the Maria Maria should speak. The ambiguous interpretation of the sentence (6) would be as follows (in the same vein of Giannakidou s approach (2007) and following her formalism): (7) a. The event of speaking happens at the utterance time b. The event of speaking happens at a future time (8) TP: t e [speak (m,e) e t t [t, ]] T : λt e [speak (m,e) e t t [t, ]] T 0 : non past: speak AspectP: λt e [speak (m,e) e t] Asp Asp 0 : Perfective VP: λt speak (m,e) λp λt λe [P (e) e t] I. t n 4 : The t it is not the utterance time II. [[non-past]] = λρ s,t λt P(t) t [t, ] (Giannakidou, 2007) The problem with sentence in (6) is that we have two possible interpretations for the event of speaking: (a) utterance time and (b) in the future time. PNP provides us only the information of non-past. However, the t does not overlap with the utterance time. We cannot locate when the time interval starts. (9) Na milisi i Maria SUBJ speak.3sg.pnp the Maria Maria should speak. 4 n = utterance time 222

(10) MoodP: t e [speak (m, e) e t t [ n, ]] na: n TP: t e [speak (m, e) e t t [ t, ]] T 0 : non past: speak AspectP: λt e [speak (m,e) e t] Asp Asp 0 : Perfective λp λt λe [P (e) e t] VP: λt speak (m,e) Notice in this derivation that adding na disambiguates the interpretation of the sentence. Now, the event of speaking starts at the time of utterance and stretches to infinity. Notice the following difference between the derivations in (8) and (10): a. LF Derivation in (7) provides: [t, ] = the event starts at a time, which is non-past (without further definitions) b. LF Derivation in (9) provides: [ n, ] = the event starts at the utterance time and stretches to infinity The na marker binds the left open boundary of the open interval that the PNP offers in the structure. The PNP is always dependent. Crucially na is not necessary in the structures with a plain FR. I propose that a plain FR can offer the temporal anchoring of the PNP verb form. In contrast with the previous theories, the DP domain of the plain FR can provide the time reference that the PNP needs. Observe the following clauses. Notice the difference between the plain FR pronoun in (11) (12) and the interrogative pronoun in (13) (14). The plain FR consist of the definite article o and the interrogative pronoun pjos ( o + pjos) (11) O-pjos er asti The- who.interrog work.3sg.pnp Whoever works (12) *O-pjos na er asti The-who.interrog SUBJ work.3sg.pnp Whoever works (13) *Pjos erghasti; 223

Who.interrog work.3sg.pnp Who should work? (14) Pjos na erghasti; Who.interrog SUBJ work.3sg.pnp Who should work? When the definite article o is taken away from the plain FR opjos, the na marker can be present. In any other case na is prohibited. Taking this into consideration, I assume that the plain FR provides a reference time to anchor the open interval of the PNP. In other words, the DP and specifically the definite article is the locus of reference time. Nevertheless, two conditions need to be satisfied; first, the DP of the plain FR must denote a plural entity, and second, the DP of the plain FR must describe a series of separate events of the same kind. Both conditions are satisfied in the case of the plain FR. Giannakidou & Cheng (2006) argue that the definite article o acts like an iota operator creating plural entities containing all those individuals who have a particular property. In addition, the plurality is that one that occupies the time interval. In this vein, this interval is the whole duration of the event in which the unbounded open interval of the PNP verb form identifies a reference time. Plural entities can affect the aspect of a verb (Kearns 2000). Plain FR in Greek denotes plural entities. Thus, they can have reference time and bind the open left boundary of the PNP verb form. I assume that the DP of the plain FR in Greek can indeed introduce time reference in the sentence by the terms we have established in the previous section. I propose the following internal structure of the DP for the plain FR in Greek following Giannakidou & Cheng (2006), who argue for a Free Choice Item analysis and Lecarme (1996) who argues for T- chains in the DP domain: Derivation of (11): O-pjos erghasti The-who.interrog (FR) work.3sg.pn Whoever works (15) DP nt i D utterance time D i CP o whp C pjos C IP 224

t 1 erghasti The DP of the plain FR in Greek can introduce time reference. In contrast with all the previous theories that argue for tense occurring in CP we showed that time reference is also possible through a DP. The nt binds D temporally thus offering a point of reference for the PNP verb. The na marker is impossible in these constructions (FR) because the PNP needs only one temporal anchoring. (16) DP D opjos 1 [+nt] CP Spec C C na [+nt] IP t 1 erghasti The DP domain (D head) and the CP domain (C head) will conflict in terms of reference of time (nt) 5. Now, if we assume that na and tha have the same semantic contribution in the structure they offer the n time- then tha also has an [nt]. However, we encounter perfectly grammatical structures that combine both a plain FR and tha but not a plain FR with na. Does this mean that our hypothesis fails to explain the incompatibility of the plain FR and na? Markers na and tha have the same semantic function. They contribute the n time. However, while they have this common property they do not overlap. I assume that the incompatibility of plain FRs with na is due to these properties of the marker. Na is both an assertive and a subordinating marker that is posited in C head. In contrast, tha is used only in assertions in T head. Nevertheless, it is not always the case that plain FRs like opjos conflict with na. Especially when a FR is followed by the connective ke (= and). DP cannot spread the reference time that the definite article triggers so it can bind the open interval of PNP because of the mediating ke (= and). That is the reason that the 5 nt = utterance time 225

presence of na (subjunctive) or an (conditional) is considered crucial after ke. The sentences that follow prove our assumptions: (16) O-pjos ke na erthi dhe me niazi The -who.interrog (FR) and SUBJ come.3sg.pnp neg me care.1sg Whoever comes, I do not care (17) *O-pjos ke erthi dhe me niazi The-who.interrog (FR) and come.3sg.pnp neg me care.1sg Whoever comes, I do not care. (18) Milisan o Janis ke *(o) Pavlos Spoke.3pl the Jonh and the Paul John and Paul spoke. 4 CONCLUSION (1) We further affirm the main points of Giannakidou (2007): that Greek needs to introduce n externally to the verb as regards the PNP. (2) We supplement her approach by showing that time reference for the PNP can also occur in the DP domain of the FR, and not only in the CP domain. Particle na is not crucial for the semantics of the plain FR. The PNP verb form can find its n-time not only in the CP domain but also in the DP. (3) Complex FR with ke an and if and ke na and (subjunctive) is a different case. Without the possibility of determiner spreading, the DP cannot serve as a reference point for the PNP. This case forces the presence of one of the particles na (subjunctive) or an (conditional) after the connective ke and. The connective ke and introduces an inference scale with concessive reading. References Agouraki, Y. (1991). A Modern Greek complementizer and its significance for Universal Grammar. UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 3, 1 24. Giannakidou, A. (2007). On the temporal properties of mood: the subjunctive revisited. To appear in Lingua, Special Issue on Mood ed. by J. Quer. Giannakidou, A & Cheng, L. (2006). (In)Definiteness, Polarity, and the Role of whmorphology in Free Choice. Journal of Semantics 23, 135 183 Lecarme, J. 1996. Tense in the nominal system: the Somali DP, in J. Lecarme, J. 226

Lowenstamm and U. Shlonsky (eds), Studies in Afroasiatic Grammar. The Hague: Holland Academic Graphics. Philippaki, I., 1992. On mood and complementizers in Modern Greek. Reading University Working Papers in Linguistics 1, 5 41. (1994). A diachronic view of the position of clitics. Studies in Greek Linguistics 15, 892 906. Thessaloniki: University of Thessaloniki. (1998). Functional categories and Modern Greek syntax. The Linguistic Review 15, 159 186. Rivero, M. L. (1994). Clause structure and V-movement in the Languages of the Balkans. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 12, 63 120 Rizzi, L. (1997). The Fine Structure of the Left Periphery, in L. Haegeman (ed.), Elements of Grammar. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Roussou, A. (2000). On the left periphery: modal particles and complementizers. Journal of Greek Linguistics 1, 65 94 (2007). In the mood for control. To appear in Lingua, Special Issue on Mood ed. by J. Quer. Terzi, A. (1992). PRO in Finite Clauses: A study of the Inflectional Heads of the Balkan Languages. Doctoral Dissertation, City University of New York. Tsimpli, I. M. (1990). Clause structure and word order in Modern Greek. UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 2, 226 255 Tsoulas, G. (1993). Remarks on the structure and interpretation of na-clauses. Studies in Greek Linguistics 14. Thessaloniki, 191 206 227