SIMILARITIES IN COVERT SYNTAX AND OVERT SYNTAX: SOME DIAGNOSTICS FROM REFLEXIVE LICENSING *

Similar documents
Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Korean ECM Constructions and Cyclic Linearization

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

SOME MINIMAL NOTES ON MINIMALISM *

Theoretical Syntax Winter Answers to practice problems

The presence of interpretable but ungrammatical sentences corresponds to mismatches between interpretive and productive parsing.

Som and Optimality Theory

Derivations (MP) and Evaluations (OT) *

Pseudo-Passives as Adjectival Passives

Argument structure and theta roles

An Introduction to the Minimalist Program

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

Control and Boundedness

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

Agree or Move? On Partial Control Anna Snarska, Adam Mickiewicz University

5 Minimalism and Optimality Theory

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

1/20 idea. We ll spend an extra hour on 1/21. based on assigned readings. so you ll be ready to discuss them in class

When a Complement PP Goes Missing: A Study on the Licensing Condition of Swiping

German Superiority *

Inleiding Taalkunde. Docent: Paola Monachesi. Blok 4, 2001/ Syntax 2. 2 Phrases and constituent structure 2. 3 A minigrammar of Italian 3

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Long-distance wh-movement. Long distance wh-movement. Islands. Islands. Locality. NP Sea. NP Sea

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

The Syntax of Coordinate Structure Complexes

Writing a composition

LIN 6520 Syntax 2 T 5-6, Th 6 CBD 234

Informatics 2A: Language Complexity and the. Inf2A: Chomsky Hierarchy

UCLA UCLA Electronic Theses and Dissertations

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Citation for published version (APA): Veenstra, M. J. A. (1998). Formalizing the minimalist program Groningen: s.n.

Derivational: Inflectional: In a fit of rage the soldiers attacked them both that week, but lost the fight.

Providing student writers with pre-text feedback

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Focusing bound pronouns

The Strong Minimalist Thesis and Bounded Optimality

Second Language Acquisition of Complex Structures: The Case of English Restrictive Relative Clauses

Intervention in Tough Constructions * Jeremy Hartman. Massachusetts Institute of Technology

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & SOCIAL STUDIES

Linguistic Variation across Sports Category of Press Reportage from British Newspapers: a Diachronic Multidimensional Analysis

The optimal placement of up and ab A comparison 1

On Labeling: Principle C and Head Movement

Backward Raising. Eric Potsdam and Maria Polinsky. automatically qualify as covert movement. We exclude such operations from consideration here.

Possessive have and (have) got in New Zealand English Heidi Quinn, University of Canterbury, New Zealand

Aspectual Classes of Verb Phrases

Update on Soar-based language processing

Part I. Figuring out how English works

Developing Grammar in Context

CHILDREN S POSSESSIVE STRUCTURES: A CASE STUDY 1. Andrew Radford and Joseph Galasso, University of Essex

The Structure of Relative Clauses in Maay Maay By Elly Zimmer

The Inclusiveness Condition in Survive-minimalism

Tagged for Deletion: A Typological Approach to VP Ellipsis in Tag Questions

(CSD) such as the naturally occurring sentences in (2), which compare the relative

LNGT0101 Introduction to Linguistics

FOCUS MARKING IN GREEK: SYNTAX OR PHONOLOGY? Michalis Georgiafentis University of Athens

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

Compositional Semantics

ON THE SYNTAX AND SEMANTICS

Hindi-Urdu Phrase Structure Annotation

A comment on the topic of topic comment

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

Syntax Parsing 1. Grammars and parsing 2. Top-down and bottom-up parsing 3. Chart parsers 4. Bottom-up chart parsing 5. The Earley Algorithm

The subject of adjectives: Syntactic position and semantic interpretation

Critical Thinking in the Workplace. for City of Tallahassee Gabrielle K. Gabrielli, Ph.D.

Intensive Writing Class

18 The syntax phonology interface

Unit 8 Pronoun References

Tap vs. Bottled Water

Curriculum and Assessment Policy

A Computational Evaluation of Case-Assignment Algorithms

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

THE ACQUISITION OF ARGUMENT ELLIPSIS IN JAPANESE: A PRELIMINARY STUDY* Koji Sugisaki Mie University

Chapter 3: Semi-lexical categories. nor truly functional. As Corver and van Riemsdijk rightly point out, There is more

Should a business have the right to ban teenagers?

LQVSumm: A Corpus of Linguistic Quality Violations in Multi-Document Summarization

Phenomena of gender attraction in Polish *

Multiattachment Syntax, Movement Effects, and Spell Out Steven Franks, Indiana University Bloomington

A is an inde nite nominal pro-form that takes antecedents. ere have

The Effect of Extensive Reading on Developing the Grammatical. Accuracy of the EFL Freshmen at Al Al-Bayt University

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Tibor Kiss Reconstituting Grammar: Hagit Borer's Exoskeletal Syntax 1

Heads and history NIGEL VINCENT & KERSTI BÖRJARS The University of Manchester

The semantics of case *

Parsing of part-of-speech tagged Assamese Texts

THE SHORT ANSWER: IMPLICATIONS FOR DIRECT COMPOSITIONALITY (AND VICE VERSA) Pauline Jacobson. Brown University

ELD CELDT 5 EDGE Level C Curriculum Guide LANGUAGE DEVELOPMENT VOCABULARY COMMON WRITING PROJECT. ToolKit

Derivational and Inflectional Morphemes in Pak-Pak Language

An Interactive Intelligent Language Tutor Over The Internet

Grade 11 Language Arts (2 Semester Course) CURRICULUM. Course Description ENGLISH 11 (2 Semester Course) Duration: 2 Semesters Prerequisite: None

ELA/ELD Standards Correlation Matrix for ELD Materials Grade 1 Reading

LING 329 : MORPHOLOGY

How to analyze visual narratives: A tutorial in Visual Narrative Grammar

Advanced Grammar in Use

Parallel Evaluation in Stratal OT * Adam Baker University of Arizona

The Real-Time Status of Island Phenomena *

Feature-Based Binding and Phase Theory. A Dissertation Presented. Andrei Antonenko. The Graduate School. in Partial Fulfillment of the.

Transcription:

SIMILARITIES IN COVERT SYNTAX AND OVERT SYNTAX: SOME DIAGNOSTICS FROM REFLEXIVE LICENSING * Mina Sugimura McGill University 1. Introduction Since Huang (1982), it has generally been believed that the Condition on Extraction Domain (CED) applies solely in overt syntax, as shown in the contrasts in (1) and (2): (1) a. * What did John go to bed [after Peter ate t]? b. Who went to bed [after Peter ate what]? (2) a. * What did [a picture of t] irritate John? b. Who said [a picture of who] irritates John? CED is a condition that forbids extraction of an element out of a syntactic island such as an adjunct or a subject clause, which are indicated by brackets above. In the (a) examples, wh-extraction out of these syntactic islands exhibits CED effects, whereas in the (b) examples, extraction is insensitive to the effects. More recently, Huang s proposal has been updated within the Minimalist Program. Ochi (1999), for example, captures the asymmetry by viewing overt and covert movement as having properties of Move and Attract (or more recently, Agree), respectively. Under this view, overt movement is always phrasal because the phonology requires phonological content of moved elements, forcing generalized pied-piping (Chomsky 1993). In contrast, covert movement is always featural since generalized pied-piping is not needed, allowing only features to move. Given the assumption that only Move is subject to the minimality condition (Chomsky 1993, and Takahashi 1994), the lack of CED effects is straightforward since Attract (or Agree) is not subject to that condition. Taking a step further, Pesetsky (2000) attempts to seriously investigate what is the nature of the movement driven by Attract. He suspects that one can simply analyze covert movement as feature movement, and discovers that covert movement is realized as phrasal movement under some circumstances. The relevant circumstance is called antecedent-contained deletion (ACD), where the elided VP requires a pronounced VP -the higher VP- as its antecedent. Consider (3): * I would like to thank to Jon Nissenbaum and Paul Hagstrom for their helpful comments and discussions. I would also like to thank Andrea Santi for her editorial help. All errors are of course mine. Actes du congrès annuel de l Association canadienne de linguistique 2008 Proceedings of the 2008 annual conference of the Canadian Linguistic Association. 2008 Mina Sugimura

2 (3) a. I need to know which girl ordered which boy that Mary (also) did [ VP Δ] to congratulate Sarah. b. * I need to know which girl Sue ordered which boy that Mary (also) did [ VP Δ] to congratulate. The fact that (3a) is grammatical suggests that the elided VP is interpreted as ordered t to congratulate Sarah via covert phrasal movement of which boy that contains ACD to the VP-external position: (4) [ CP which girl [ DP which boy that Mary (also) did [ VP Δ]] 2 [ VP ordered t 2 to congratulate Sarah]] 1 In contrast, the fact that (3b) is ungrammatical suggests that covert phrasal movement of which boy containing ACD is unavailable in this configuration. 2 According to Pesetsky, covert phrasal movement is possible only for a structurally lower wh-phrase (=3a), but not for a structurally higher wh-phrase (=3b). When the phrasal movement is unavailable, covert movement is realized as feature movement. Thus, the grammatical contrast in (3) follows from the (un)successful licensing of ACD. Summarizing so far, covert movement has been given a special status in all of the analyses mentioned above. Huang (1982) stipulates that covert movement is immune from CED. Ochi (1999) argues that covert phrasal movement does not exist: rather, all wh-in-situ are licensed via Attract. Pesetsky (2000) reports that covert phrasal movement does exist in a certain environment, but feature movement takes its place in any other case. These theoretical moves leave us with important questions: What is covert movement in the first place, and what distinguishes covert movement from overt movement? Nissenbaum (2000) takes this longstanding issue seriously, and in fact, reverses these widespread assumptions. He argues that covert movement should not necessarily be treated as a special case of grammar: rather, covert movement has more in common with overt movement than has been generally assumed. He argues that the artificial difference between these two components lies in the Spell-Out timing: that is, pre-spell-out movement is overt, whereas post-spell-out movement is covert. On this view, only one type of movement exists, namely, phrasal movement. Thus, there is no distinction between overt movement and covert movement, and all of the grammatical conditions consequently hold only at the interface level (LF and PF). In this paper, I further investigate the nature of covert movement by examining specific constructions that none of the above analyses have dealt with. I then show that my data support Nissenbaum s view of movement, pointing out that in fact, covert movement displays exactly the same effects as overt 1 Here, I assume which boy containing ACD tucks in underneath which girl in Richard s (1997) sense. I will come back to the issue later on in the next section. 2 The badness of the sentence is indeed due to the failure of licensing ACD: since a sentence like I need to know which girl Sue ordered which boy to congratulate is grammatical, (apparent) superiority violation is irrelevant here. 2

3 movement does. This finding leads us to conclude that Huang and Ochi s separation of covert movement from overt movement or Pesetsky s subdivision of covert movement cannot be retained as they are. The organization of the rest of the paper is as follows: Section 2 introduces Nissenbaum s (2000) work, with crucial examples involving Condition A, where he shows that despite the widespread belief that only overt movement can license Condition A, covert movement can do so as well. Based on this finding, I raise a question in section 3 for Pesetsky s (2000) assumption that covert phrasal movement is possible only for a structurally lower wh-phrase (henceforth, wh 2 ), but not for a structurally higher wh-phrase (henceforth, wh 1 ). I show that the structurally higher wh-phrase in fact undergoes covert phrasal movement by demonstrating that the movement enables a reflexive contained in a wh 1 to be bound. I also show that the same holds in constructions where the antecedent of a bound-variable is provided by covert phrasal movement of wh 1. Together with these findings, I claim that covert phrasal movement indeed occurs no matter what the structural configuration is there for wh-in-situ. In Section 4 I turn to the interaction between CED effects and covert phrasal movement. Using the diagnostics of Condition A, I show that CED effects in fact show up in covert syntax as well, unlike Huang and Ochi argue. Section 5 concludes this paper. 2. Nissenbaum s (2000) Argument for Covert Phrasal Movement One of the biggest issues that had been differentiating covert movement of wh-in-situ from overt wh-movement is incapability of licensing Condition A: (5) a. Mary knows which picture of herself John is looking at_ b. * Mary knows John is looking at a picture of herself. c. * Mary knows which man was looking at which picture of herself. (Nissenbaum 2000:143) The grammatical contrast between (5a) and (5b) illustrates the fact that movement is mandatory for licensing Condition A. (5a) and (5c) appear to indicate, however, that the movement has to be overt, not covert. Nissenbaum (2000) first doubts this widespread belief, and seeks an independent reason that covert wh-movement appears to fail to feed Condition A. He then reveals a fact that we have all taken for granted: the output of covert movement in (5c) results in a structure like (6): (6) Mary knows [which picture of herself] 2 [which man] 1 t 1 was looking at t 2 In (6), which picture of herself moves above the outermost segment that contains which man, and thereby creates the configuration where herself should be able to be bound by Mary, contrary to fact. However, if we assume that (6) is the wrong LF representation, and that 3

4 Richards s (1997) tucking-in condition (TIC) in (7) is the way that movement is always supposed to be, the LF structure of (5c) should be like (8): (7) Tucking-in condition (TIC): Movement must tuck in below the outermost segment. (8) Mary knows [which man] 1 [which picture of herself] 2 t 1 was looking at t 2 Notice that unlike (6), movement of which picture of herself targets below the outermost segment in (8). If (8) is the actual LF representation of (5c), then the sentence no longer constitutes a convincing argument against either covert wh-movement itself or Condition A applying at LF. In other words, even if we assume this, herself cannot be locally bound by Mary in any event, because the intervening subject which man blocks the binding. This in turn suggests that once we set up a construction where TIC is factored out for Condition A, covert phrasal movement may obtain a chance to feed condition A. Thus, in principle, a reflexive should be able to be locally bound in any of the positions where the arrow points at in (9): (9) WH-1 [ [ [WH-2 reflexive] ]] The following examples show that the prediction is borne out: (10) a. Which boy thinks Mary 1 wants him to buy which picture of herself 1? b. Which boy [ TP t [ vp thinks [ CP Mary 1 [ vp wants him to [ vp buy [ NP which picture of herself 1 ]]]] (Nissenbaum 2000:146) In (10b) TIC is irrelevant for reflexive binding since wh 1, which boy, does not intervene between herself and Mary. The wh-in-situ which picture of herself undergoes successive-cyclic covert phrasal movement, and Condition A is satisfied at the appropriate vp peripheral position (the relevant landing site is circled). Note that the grammaticality of (10a) is indeed due to the movement of wh-in-situ, and is not due to the long-distance (logophoric) binding of the reflexive, as shown in (11): (11) * Which boy thinks that Mary 1 wants him to buy a picture of herself 1? In (11), the wh-in-situ is replaced by an indefinite NP which cannot undergo movement. The ungrammaticality of (11) indicates that movement is in fact 4

5 necessary for reflexive binding. Notice that this is unexpected under Ochi s Attract-type analysis for covert movement. If covert movement is always featural, then, a sentence like (10a) would never become grammatical. One might argue, however, that feature movement suffices to create a new binding/scope relation (Chomsky 1993), and thereby saves the sentence like (10a). However, if this were the case, as Ochi (1998) argued (originally due to Lasnik (1995)), the following sentence should be ungrammatical: (12) Himself 1, John 1 thinks that Mary likes t 1. (cf. *John 1 thinks that Mary likes himself 1.) In (12), the reflexive takes the matrix subject John as its antecedent. The derivation of (12) has two possibilities: (13) a. [Top [John thinks that Mary likes himself]] [+Top] [FF] b. [ himself [Top [ John [ t [ thinks [ t that [ Mary [ t TOPP TP vp VP CP TP vp [ likes t]]]]]]]]]]]] VP Here, what triggers movement of a reflexive is a Topic head (Top), and the reflexive has a formal feature that is relevant for binding (FF). (13a) is a representation under the feature movement analysis, whereas (13b) is the one under the phrasal movement analysis. Notice that in (13a), the anaphor can never be licensed. Since feature movement takes place in one step, a formal feature (FF) of himself does not occupy the intermediate position where it could be bound by John. In contrast, in (13b) the grammaticality is correctly predicted: phrasal movement of himself stops by the appropriate intermediate position (the higher vp) for binding due to the nature of successive cyclicity for phrasal movement. The grammaticality of (12) indeed tells us that phrasal movement is a necessary condition for a binding/scope configuration to be created, in contradiction to what Chomsky argues. Summarizing this section, we have seen that a wh-in-situ undergoes covert phrasal movement, and that movement is capable of feeding Condition A. In the following section, I further investigate whether covert phrasal movement always happens by using diagnostics of Condition A. 3. Condition A as A True Diagnostic for Covert Phrasal Movement Recall that Pesetsky argues that covert phrasal movement is only possible for a structurally lower wh-phrase (wh 2 ), but not for a structurally higher wh-phrase 5

6 (wh 1 ). In the previous section, we have only considered the case where the structurally lower wh-phrase undergoes phrasal movement. In this section, I further examine the case where the higher wh-phrase is forced to undergo phrasal movement to satisfy Condition A. Consider the following examples, where a reflexive is contained inside a wh 1 -in-situ: 3 (14) a. Which statue 2 did John 1 persuade Mary to say which picture of himself 1 would fall on t 2? b. * Which statue 2 did John 1 persuade Mary to say a picture of himself 1 would fall on t 2? c. Which statue [ TP John [ vp persuade [Mary 1 to [ vp say [ CP [ NP which picture of herself 1 ] would fall on t ]]]]] (15) a. Which book did John 1 persuade Mary to say which likeness of himself 1 would buy? b. * Which book did John 1 persuade Mary to say that a likeness of himself 1 would buy? c. Which book [ TP John [ vp persuade [Mary 1 to [ vp say [ CP [ NP which likeness of herself 1 ] would buy t ]]]]] What is striking here is the grammaticality of both (a) examples. Notice that if Pesetsky s (2000) claim is correct, then the higher wh-phrase must have undergone feature movement instead of phrasal movement in the covert syntax. If so, both (a) examples should be ungrammatical due to the failure of licensing a reflexive, contrary to fact. As shown by the ungrammaticality of both (b) examples, reflexives cannot be locally bound without covert phrasal wh-movement. Hence, the acceptability of both (a) examples convincingly suggests that the higher wh-phrase in fact undergoes covert phrasal movement. 3 The reason for involving more than one embedded clause in these sentences is that reflexives inside the embedded subject position are known to be bindable from the matrix clause: (i) a. John said that pictures of himself were on sale b. John said that pictures of himself had fallen on Mary c. John said that likenesses of himself would soon buy books Thus, one more clause needs to be embedded between their intended antecedents and reflexives: (ii) a. *John said Mary thinks that pictures of himself are on sale. b. *John said Cathy thinks that pictures of himself had fallen on Mary. c. *John said Mary thinks that likenesses of himself would soon buy books. In light of this, the (i) examples are predicted to be grammatical even if Pesetsky's claim is correct. Thus, the examples in (14) and (15) are well constructed in a way that the reflexives cannot be locally bound without covert wh-movement, as shown by the ungrammaticality of the (b) examples. 6

7 Another piece of evidence for covert phrasal movement of wh 1 -in-situ comes from the availability of a bound pronoun interpretation. Before discussing these crucial examples, the following control cases need to be confirmed first: (16) a. Which man 1 did which woman [ VP claim that Mary dislikes t 1 before visiting his 1 wife]? b. Which woman [ VP claimed that Mary dislikes which man 1 ] [before visiting his 1 wife]? c. * Which woman [ VP claimed that Mary dislikes no one 1 ] [before visiting his 1 wife]? In all of the examples above, the adjunct clause containing a bound pronoun unambiguously modifies the higher VP clause (i.e. which man is the visitor, not Mary) since the present tense of the lower verb dislike is incompatible with the before-clause. (16a)shows that overt movement of the structurally lower wh-phrase, which man, enables a bound variable to be licensed, without causing a Weak Cross Over (WCO) violation. 4 (16b) confirms the fact that the same holds for covert wh-movement: thus, the bound variable is licensed by a wh-in-situ, which man. Most importantly, (16c) shows that such licensing is indeed due to the availability of movement: A quantifier no one, which cannot undergo movement across the clause boundary, fails to license a bound variable, rendering the sentence ungrammatical. Bearing these in mind, let us turn to the crucial cases where the wh-in-situ is structurally higher: (17) a. Which woman 2 did you [ VP claim that which man 1 dislikes t 2 ] [before visitinghis 1 wife]? b. * Which woman 2 did you [ VP claim that no one dislikes t 2 ] [before visiting his 1 wife]? 4 Insensitivity to WCO can be considered as an instance of Chomsky s (1976) Leftness Condition effect, which states that a pronoun cannot be coindexed with a variable to its right. Consequently, a quantifier cannot move to the left of a variable. The following examples further support this idea: (i) Who [said that he d enjoyed what (movie)] [in order to get you to see it]? (ii) Which boy did you [refuse to introduce to every girl] [in order to make her angry]? (Nissenbaum 2000) In (i), the rational clause unambiguously modifies the higher clause since enjoy, a psych predicate, is incompatible with rationals, as indicated by (iii): (iii) # I enjoyed that movie in order to impress my friends. Similarly, in (ii), the rational clause modifies the embedded vp under the most natural reading. Yet, these examples are fully acceptable, and do not exhibit WCO violation. Thus, these data confirm the irrelevance of WCO effects in examples in (16) and (17). 7

8 In (17a), the structurally higher wh-in-situ, which man, is the only possible binder for a bound variable. In (17b), the wh-in-situ is replaced by a quantifier, no one, which is a potential binder of the bound variable. The grammatical contrast between (17a) and (17b) suggests that in (17a), the structurally higher wh-in-situ has undergone covert phrasal movement. The acceptability of (14a), (15a), and (17a) evidently shows that the structurally higher wh-phrase in fact undergoes covert phrasal movement, as opposed to Pesetsky s analysis. The data in fact strengthen Nissenbaum s view that covert movement and overt movement are the same: i.e. covert movement is always phrasal. This in turn suggests that classifying covert movement in terms of structural hierarchy cannot be as simple as Pesetsky argues. In fact, dividing covert movement into phrasal and featural domains is certainly less economical than unifying all movement. If covert movement is always phrasal, there is no need to assume an additional operation such as feature movement. Accordingly, a separate operation for covert movement and overt movement is no longer necessary. 4. CED Effects and Covert Phrasal Movement Recall that at the outset of this paper, I mentioned that it has been assumed that CED does not apply in covert syntax. However, if it is actually the case that overt movement and covert movement are essentially the same, we expect to see the CED effects in covert syntax as well. In fact, this prediction is borne out. Consider (18) and (19): (18) * Which woman 2 did John 1 say t 2 would be upset [if we saw which picture ofhimself 1 ]? (19) * Which man 1 persuaded Mary to say [a copy of which picture of himself 1 ] fell on her foot? (18) and (19) are adjunct island and subject island cases, respectively. In both examples, the extraction of wh-in-situ out of these syntactic islands renders the sentences completely ungrammatical, parallel to the extraction in overt syntax, as shown in (20) and (21): (20) * Which woman would John be upset [if we invite t (to the party)]? (21) * Which picture did [a copy of t] fall on her foot? Given the data above, the widespread belief about immunity to CED effects is now reversed: covert movement in fact obeys CED as does overt movement. Now, the obvious question to be addressed is why the following cases do not show the CED effects: (22) Which man will be upset if we invite which philosopher? 8

9 (23) Which man said a copy of which picture would fall on her foot? Since I have been arguing that all the wh-phrases undergo covert phrasal movement on a par with overt movement, (22) and (23) should be ungrammatical due to the CED effect, contrary to fact. A natural assumption to be made then is that in-situ wh-phrases actually undergo phrasal movement, but only to the periphery of the island clause: that is, they do not move out of the island in order to obey CED. Thus, the LF representations of (22) and (23) would be in fact like (24) and (25), respectively: (24) [ CP which man 1 t 1 will be upset [ CP which philosopher 2 [if we invite t 2 ]]] (25) [ CP which man 1 t 1 said [ vp [a copy of which picture] would fall on her foot]] Supporting evidence for the movement inside the syntactic island is given in (26): (26) Which woman said John 2 would be upset if Mark 1 claimed Mary saw which picture of himself 1/*2? In (26) himself can take Mark as its antecedent inside the adjunct clause, but not John outside the adjunct clause. The contrast becomes even sharper in the following cases, where the intended antecedent is either preceded by a female name, or followed by it, as shown below: (27) a. Which woman said Sue would be upset if Mark 1 claimed Mary saw which picture of himself 1? b. * Which woman said Mark 1 would be upset if Sue claimed Mary saw which picture of himself 1? These data suggest that which picture of himself in (27a), for example, actually moves from the original position to the edge of the adjunct clause, but it stays inside the adjunct island, as shown in (28): (28) Which woman said Sue would be upset [ CP [which picture of himself 1 ] 2 if Mark 1 claimed Mary saw t 2 ] As Richards (2000) discussed in his paper, such internal movement of a wh-phrase inside an island is independently motivated cross-linguistically. Consider first the English pied-piping cases in (29): (29) a. [Who] did you see? b. [Whose book] did you buy? In the examples above, a wh-phrase can move by itself (29a), or with its pied-piping NP phrase (29b). 9

10 However, the following examples show that there is some restriction on pied-piping: (30) a.* [Pictures of what] did you see? b.* [Fond of what] is he? Richards pointed out that the difference between the examples in (29) and (30) is that a wh-operator is exhaustively c-commanding its c-command domain (i.e., its scope) in the former, while that is not the case in the latter. Thus, he concludes that the condition on pied-piping is that in order to pied-pipe a constituent XP, the wh-operator has to be in the specifier of XP. This condition is actually attested cross-linguistically: in languages like Basque and German, movement of a wh-operator to the clause periphery can be seen overtly, as shown in (31) and (32): (31) Basque (originally due to Ortiz de Urbina 1989) [Nor joango d-ela ] estan du Jon-ek? who go AUX Q say AUX John- ERG Who has John said will go? (32) German Den Wagen, [den zu kaufen er sich schon] lange the car which to buy he self already long vorgenommen hatte planned had the car which he had planned to buy for a long time In (31) and (32), a pied-piped clause is indicated by dotted underlining, and movement of a wh-operator inside the clause is indicated by an arrow. Notice that this configuration is quite similar to what I am assuming for the LF structure of (27a) and illustrated in (28). The only difference between Richards s examples and mine is that either this internal movement of a wh-operator is overt or covert. Thus, LF wh-movement to the periphery of the syntactic island is well-motivated from Richards cross-linguistic point of view as well. 5 5 A question to be asked is how multiple interrogatives such as (22) can obtain a semantic interpretation without moving a wh-in-situ to the matrix CP. One possible way for the wh-in-situ to get a scope over the entire root clause is that the whole adjunct clause undergoes pied-piping (Nishigauchi 1990). 10

11 5. Conclusion I have shown that covert movement displays the same effects as overt movement, in support of Nissenbaum (2000). As a consequence, I have taken a position against Huang and Ochi s separation of covert movement from overt movement, and raised questions for Pesetsky s subdivision of covert movement by showing that there are cases where a wh-in-situ always undergoes phrasal movement. I further showed that there are CED effects in covert syntax, contrary to what has been assumed so far. The apparent lack of CED effects is not due to either the absence of movement or feature movement of wh-in-situ. The phrasal movement does exist but is implemented only inside syntactic islands, obeying CED. The overt counterpart of this internal movement in Basque and German further strengthens the idea that overt movement and covert movement are essentially the same. References Chomsky, Noam. 1976. Conditions on rules of grammar. Linguistic Analysis 2: 303-351. Chomsky, Noam. 1993. A minimalist program for linguistic theory. In The view from Building 20, eds. K. Hale and S. Keyser, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. [Also published in Noam Chomsky, The Minimalist Program, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.] Huang, C-.T. James. 1982. Logical relations in Chinese and the theory of grammar. Doctoral dissertation, MIT. Lasnik, Howard. 1995. Last Resort and Attract F. In Proceedings of the 6th Annual Meetings of the Formal Linguistics Society of Mid-America, eds. L. Gabriele, D. Hardison and R. Westmoreland, 62-81. Indiana University. Nishigauchi, Taisuke. 1990. Quantification in the Theory of Grammar. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Nissenbaum, Jonathan. 2000. Investigations of covert phrasal movement. Doctoral dissertation, MIT. Ochi, Masao 1999. Constraints on feature checking. Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut.. Ortiz de Urbina, Jon. 1989. Parameters in the Grammar of Basque. Dordrecht: Foris Pesetsky, David. 2000. Phrasal Movement and Its Kin. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Richards, Norvin. 1997. What moves where in which language? Doctoral dissertation, MIT. Richards, Norvin. 2000. An island effect in Japanese. Journal of East Asian Linguistics: 187-205. Takahashi, Daiko. 1994. Minimality of movement. Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut. 11