Weak Crossover and the Direct Association Hypothesis

Similar documents
Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

Som and Optimality Theory

The presence of interpretable but ungrammatical sentences corresponds to mismatches between interpretive and productive parsing.

THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & SOCIAL STUDIES

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

Control and Boundedness

The Interface between Phrasal and Functional Constraints

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Second Language Acquisition of Complex Structures: The Case of English Restrictive Relative Clauses

Feature-Based Grammar

Inleiding Taalkunde. Docent: Paola Monachesi. Blok 4, 2001/ Syntax 2. 2 Phrases and constituent structure 2. 3 A minigrammar of Italian 3

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

LFG Semantics via Constraints

Switched Control and other 'uncontrolled' cases of obligatory control

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Argument structure and theta roles

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

"f TOPIC =T COMP COMP... OBJ

Type-driven semantic interpretation and feature dependencies in R-LFG

The Pennsylvania State University. The Graduate School. College of the Liberal Arts THE TEACHABILITY HYPOTHESIS AND CONCEPT-BASED INSTRUCTION

The Structure of Relative Clauses in Maay Maay By Elly Zimmer

Hans-Ulrich Block, Hans Haugeneder Siemens AG, MOnchen ZT ZTI INF W. Germany. (2) [S' [NP who][s does he try to find [NP e]]s IS' $=~

PROJECTIONS AND GLUE FOR CLAUSE-UNION COMPLEX PREDICATES. Avery D Andrews The Australian National University. Proceedings of the LFG07 Conference

Towards a Machine-Learning Architecture for Lexical Functional Grammar Parsing. Grzegorz Chrupa la

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

Informatics 2A: Language Complexity and the. Inf2A: Chomsky Hierarchy

Theoretical Syntax Winter Answers to practice problems

ENGBG1 ENGBL1 Campus Linguistics. Meeting 2. Chapter 7 (Morphology) and chapter 9 (Syntax) Pia Sundqvist

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

Construction Grammar. University of Jena.

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Korean ECM Constructions and Cyclic Linearization

LNGT0101 Introduction to Linguistics

Derivations (MP) and Evaluations (OT) *

Chapter 4: Valence & Agreement CSLI Publications

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

Heads and history NIGEL VINCENT & KERSTI BÖRJARS The University of Manchester

Interfacing Phonology with LFG

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

Grammars & Parsing, Part 1:

Constructions with Lexical Integrity *

Negation through reduplication and tone: implications for the LFG/PFM interface 1

The optimal placement of up and ab A comparison 1

Chapter 3: Semi-lexical categories. nor truly functional. As Corver and van Riemsdijk rightly point out, There is more

The building blocks of HPSG grammars. Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG) HPSG grammars from a linguistic perspective

An Introduction to the Minimalist Program

Derivational: Inflectional: In a fit of rage the soldiers attacked them both that week, but lost the fight.

Structure-Preserving Extraction without Traces

Improved Effects of Word-Retrieval Treatments Subsequent to Addition of the Orthographic Form

Hindi-Urdu Phrase Structure Annotation

Adapting Stochastic Output for Rule-Based Semantics

ON THE SYNTAX AND SEMANTICS

An Interactive Intelligent Language Tutor Over The Internet

Pseudo-Passives as Adjectival Passives

On the Notion Determiner

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

A relational approach to translation

The Real-Time Status of Island Phenomena *

Some Principles of Automated Natural Language Information Extraction

Syntax Parsing 1. Grammars and parsing 2. Top-down and bottom-up parsing 3. Chart parsers 4. Bottom-up chart parsing 5. The Earley Algorithm

Compositional Semantics

Focusing bound pronouns

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

A Computational Evaluation of Case-Assignment Algorithms

Indeterminacy by Underspecification Mary Dalrymple (Oxford), Tracy Holloway King (PARC) and Louisa Sadler (Essex) (9) was: ( case) = nom ( case) = acc

Parsing of part-of-speech tagged Assamese Texts

Writing a composition

Hindi Aspectual Verb Complexes

cmp-lg/ Jul 1995

BULATS A2 WORDLIST 2

Language acquisition: acquiring some aspects of syntax.

Natural Language Processing. George Konidaris

Improving coverage and parsing quality of a large-scale LFG for German

Linguistic Inquiry, Volume 35, Number 1, Winter 2004, pp (Article)

Phenomena of gender attraction in Polish *

1/20 idea. We ll spend an extra hour on 1/21. based on assigned readings. so you ll be ready to discuss them in class

The semantics of case *

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

In search of ambiguity

Agree or Move? On Partial Control Anna Snarska, Adam Mickiewicz University

Context Free Grammars. Many slides from Michael Collins

Developing a TT-MCTAG for German with an RCG-based Parser

LING 329 : MORPHOLOGY

Spanish progressive aspect in stochastic OT

The Development of Linking Theory in lfg

L1 and L2 acquisition. Holger Diessel

What Can Neural Networks Teach us about Language? Graham Neubig a2-dlearn 11/18/2017

Prediction of Maximal Projection for Semantic Role Labeling

Basic Parsing with Context-Free Grammars. Some slides adapted from Julia Hirschberg and Dan Jurafsky 1

Citation for published version (APA): Veenstra, M. J. A. (1998). Formalizing the minimalist program Groningen: s.n.

FOREWORD.. 5 THE PROPER RUSSIAN PRONUNCIATION. 8. УРОК (Unit) УРОК (Unit) УРОК (Unit) УРОК (Unit) 4 80.

18 The syntax phonology interface

Part I. Figuring out how English works

THE SHORT ANSWER: IMPLICATIONS FOR DIRECT COMPOSITIONALITY (AND VICE VERSA) Pauline Jacobson. Brown University

Update on Soar-based language processing

LTAG-spinal and the Treebank

Transcription:

Weak Crossover and the Direct Association Hypothesis Prerna Nadathur Department of Linguistics, Philology & Phonetics University of Oxford July 19, 2013

Outline

Outline Weak crossover

Outline Weak crossover Two LFG treatments Bresnan 1995 (trace-based) Dalrymple, Kaplan & King 2001 (traceless)

Outline Weak crossover Two LFG treatments Bresnan 1995 (trace-based) Dalrymple, Kaplan & King 2001 (traceless) Direct association

Outline Weak crossover Two LFG treatments Bresnan 1995 (trace-based) Dalrymple, Kaplan & King 2001 (traceless) Direct association Additional data Pied-piping Double-object constructions and objectivity distinctions Adjuncts and syntactic prominence Multiple gaps

Outline Weak crossover Two LFG treatments Bresnan 1995 (trace-based) Dalrymple, Kaplan & King 2001 (traceless) Direct association Additional data Pied-piping Double-object constructions and objectivity distinctions Adjuncts and syntactic prominence Multiple gaps Conclusions Directions for further inquiry Synthetic data Summary

Weak Crossover (Postal 1971, Wasow 1972) Transformational grammar regards wh-questions as formed when a wh-operator is fronted. A weak crossover violation occurs in cases like (1), when the operator must pass over a coreferential pronoun on its way to the head of a sentence. Example (1) a. His i mother greeted him i. b. *Who i did his i mother greet?

Weak Crossover (Postal 1971, Wasow 1972) Transformational grammar regards wh-questions as formed when a wh-operator is fronted. A weak crossover violation occurs in cases like (1), when the operator must pass over a coreferential pronoun on its way to the head of a sentence. Example (1) a. His i mother greeted him i. b. *Who i did his i mother greet? The acceptability difference only occurs when operator movement would involve crossing the pronoun: both examples in (2) are acceptable as indexed. Example (2) a. He i greeted his i mother. b. Who i greeted his i mother?

Bresnan s (1995) account of weak crossover Bresnan represents traces in the c-structure of an example like (1)b (based on the treatment of long-distance dependencies in Kaplan & Bresnan 1982). Traces therefore also correspond to an f-structure, and in particular the same f-structure as the operator.

C- and f-structures for (1)b (Bresnan) Example (3) a. *Who i did his i mother greet? b. NP CP C c. PRED greet< f 1, f 2 > FOCUS f 2 : [ PRED who ] [ [ ] SPEC PRED pro SUBJ f 1 : PRED mother ] who i C IP OBJ f 2 did NP I Det N VP his i mother V NP greet t i

Bresnan (1995) continued For Bresnan, coreference phenomena are broadly constrained by two principles:

Bresnan (1995) continued For Bresnan, coreference phenomena are broadly constrained by two principles: Syntactic rank comes from the functional hierarchy (Keenan & Comrie 1977) SUBJ > OBJ > OBL > COMP (from Bresnan)

Bresnan (1995) continued For Bresnan, coreference phenomena are broadly constrained by two principles: Syntactic rank comes from the functional hierarchy (Keenan & Comrie 1977) SUBJ > OBJ > OBL > COMP (from Bresnan) Linear order is governed by f-precedence: Let µ be the mapping from c-structure nodes to f-structures, and f and g be f-structures. Then f f-precedes g iff µ 1 (f ), µ 1 (g), and all nodes in µ 1 (f ) precede some node in µ 1 (g)

Prominence constraints To avoid a weak crossover violation for Bresnan (1995), a wh-question with coreferenced operator and pronoun must obey the following prominence constraints. Syntactic prominence: An f-structure containing the pronoun may not be higher in syntactic rank than an f-structure containing the operator. Linear prominence: The pronoun must not f-precede the operator. *(Bresnan argues that the relative significance of these constraints varies crosslinguistically. Both must be satisfied in English.)

Bresnan (1995) continued Example (3) is ungrammatical because it violates both prominence constraints: The operator is in the OBJ f-structure, and the pronoun is in higher-ranked SUBJ The pronoun appears before the trace (which is in the same f-structure as the operator) and so f-precedes the operator

Bresnan (1995) continued Example (3) is ungrammatical because it violates both prominence constraints: The operator is in the OBJ f-structure, and the pronoun is in higher-ranked SUBJ The pronoun appears before the trace (which is in the same f-structure as the operator) and so f-precedes the operator On the other hand, (2)b is fine: Example (2) b. Who i (t i ) greeted his i mother? The operator has rank SUBJ, while the pronoun is in OBJ; since both operator and trace occur before the pronoun, linear prominence is satisfied as well.

Dalrymple, Kaplan & King 2001 Dalrymple, Kaplan & King (2001) propose a revision of Bresnan s account that maintains the idea of prominence constraints but eliminates the need for a trace. This is based on Kaplan & Zaenen s (1989) treatment of long-distance dependencies via functional uncertainty.

Dalrymple, Kaplan & King 2001 Dalrymple, Kaplan & King (2001) propose a revision of Bresnan s account that maintains the idea of prominence constraints but eliminates the need for a trace. This is based on Kaplan & Zaenen s (1989) treatment of long-distance dependencies via functional uncertainty. The idea underlying the revision is that linear prominence requirements between an operator and a pronoun are determined by overt material which indicates the syntactic role of the displaced phrase, rather than by the position of a covert trace.

C- and f-structures for (3) (Dalrymple et al) Example (4) a. *Who i did his i mother greet? b. NP CP C c. PRED greet< f 1, f 2 > FOCUS f 2 : [ PRED who ] [ [ ] SPEC PRED pro SUBJ f 1 : PRED mother ] who i C IP OBJ f 2 did NP I Det his i N mother VP V greet

Dalrymple et al continued Example (5) *Who i did Sue talk about his i mother to (t i )?

Dalrymple et al continued Example (5) *Who i did Sue talk about his i mother to (t i )? Both extracted element are pronoun are OBL; (5) is fine on syntactic prominence

Dalrymple et al continued Example (5) *Who i did Sue talk about his i mother to (t i )? Both extracted element are pronoun are OBL; (5) is fine on syntactic prominence For Bresnan: the trace is at the end of the sentence, so the pronoun f-precedes the operator

Dalrymple et al continued Example (5) *Who i did Sue talk about his i mother to (t i )? Both extracted element are pronoun are OBL; (5) is fine on syntactic prominence For Bresnan: the trace is at the end of the sentence, so the pronoun f-precedes the operator Dalrymple et al instead consider the overt preposition to the revised proposal holds that the presence of to after the pronoun is what rules (5) out.

Revised prominence constraints Dalrymple et al introduce coarguments to handle this formally: The coarguments of a predicate (e.g. talk ) are all of its adjuncts and arguments. CoargPro is the coargument f-structure containing the pronoun CoargOp is the coargument f-structure containing the operator

Revised prominence constraints Dalrymple et al introduce coarguments to handle this formally: The coarguments of a predicate (e.g. talk ) are all of its adjuncts and arguments. CoargPro is the coargument f-structure containing the pronoun CoargOp is the coargument f-structure containing the operator The prominence contraints are then: Syntactic prominence: CoargOp must be at least as high as CoargPro on the functional hierarchy. Linear prominence: CoargOp must f-precede the pronoun.

Revised prominence constraints Example (5) *Who i did Sue talk about his i mother to (t i )? PRED talk< SUBJ, OBL to, OBL about > FOCUS f 1 : [ PRED who ] [ ] SUBJ [ PRED Sue ] PRED to<obj> OBL to OBJ f 1 PRED [ about<obj> [ ] SPEC PRED pro OBJ PRED mother OBL about ] CoargOp is the f-structure OBL to ; CoargPro is OBL about CoargOp contains both the to and who nodes The pronoun precedes to, so CoargPro f-precedes CoargOp, and (5) violates linear prominence

Dalrymple et al continued Example (6) Who i did Sue talk to about his i mother? The revised constraints correctly predict grammaticality here. They also make the correct predictions for (2)b and (3): Example (2) b. Who i greeted his i mother? Example (3) *Who i did his i mother greet?

A direct account

A direct account Pickering & Barry s (1991) Direct Association Hypothesis proposes that a link is made directly between an extracted element and the predicate or proposition that selects for it. Example (6) Who i did Sue talk to about his i mother?

A direct account Pickering & Barry s (1991) Direct Association Hypothesis proposes that a link is made directly between an extracted element and the predicate or proposition that selects for it. Example (6) Who i did Sue talk to about his i mother? A direct link between the operator and the item selecting for it captures Dalrymple et al s intuition about overt syntactic information, but eliminates the need for coargument structure. Following Dalrymple & King (2013), the subcategorizing element will be referred to as the anchor.

Weak crossover by direct association Example (7) *[Who i ] Op did [his i ] Pro mother [greet] Anch? Example (8) [Who i ] Op [greeted] Anch [his i ] Pro mother? Example (9) *[Who i ] Op did Sue talk about [his i ] Pro mother [to] Anch? Example (10) [Who i ] Op did Sue talk [to] Anch about [his i ] Pro mother? In (7) and (9) alone, the anchor follows the pronoun. These are the examples involving weak crossover violations.

Re-revised prominence constraints According to the observation above, I revise linear prominence as follows: Linear prominence: the anchor (of the operator) must precede the pronoun. Syntactic prominence remains as in Bresnan 1995: Syntactic prominence: An f-structure containing the pronoun may not be higher in syntactic rank than an f-structure containing the operator.

Additional data Example (11) [To whom i ] Op did you [give] Anch [her i ] Pro book (t i )? Example (12) [In whose i hand] Op did you [put] Anch [his i ] Pro pen (t i )? Example (13) (?) [To whom i ] Op did you [introduce] Anch [her i ] Pro neighbors (t i )? Bresnan predicts ungrammaticality here The anchor account predicts acceptability Judgements elicited from speakers of American English have (11) ruled grammatical, (12) ruled grammatical by a majority, and (13) ruled grammatical half the time

Double object constructions The dative alternation: Example (14) a. John gave Mary the book. b. John gave the book to Mary. The status of the objects in (12) and (13) is similarly debated; Dryer (1986) suggests split objectivity. English double objects may be ambiguous in mental representation; this uncertainty about syntactic rank is reflected in judgements for (11)-(13).

Additional data continued Example (15) [Whose i book] Op did you [give] Anch [her i ] Pro friend (t i )? Example (16) [To whom i ] Op did Sue [talk] Anch (t i ) about [his i ] Pro mother (t i )? (15) unequivocally supports the anchor account over the trace account (16) has an ambiguous extraction site maybe itself a mark against the trace account On the whole, separating anchor and trace favours anchor account

Objectivity distinctions Example (17) a. (?) [Who i ] Op did you [give] Anch (t i ) [her i ] Pro book? b. (?) [Whose i book] Op did you [give] Anch [her i ] Pro (t i )? (17)a and b both satisfy linear prominence on the anchor account Direct objectivity would block (17)a on syntactic prominence, and permit (17)b Primary objectivity would allow (17)a and block (17)b

Adjuncts and syntactic prominence Example (18) *[With whom i ] Op did Jessica [visit] (Anch) [his i ] Pro cousin (t i )? Example (19) *[In whose i car] Op did Anne [meet] (Anch) [him i ] Pro (t i )? Example (20) *[From whose i house] Op did George [call] (Anch) [her i ] Pro (t i )?

Multiple anchor sites Parasitic gaps (Engdahl 1983): Example (21) (?) Who i did you advise t i before his i wife divorced i,p?

Multiple anchor sites Parasitic gaps (Engdahl 1983): Example (21) (?) Who i did you advise t i before his i wife divorced i,p? Tough construction: Example (22) Who i t i will be easy for us to get his i mother to talk to t i?

Multiple anchor sites Parasitic gaps (Engdahl 1983): Example (21) (?) Who i did you advise t i before his i wife divorced i,p? Tough construction: Example (22) Who i t i will be easy for us to get his i mother to talk to t i? Bresnan 1995 rules these out If first possible anchor site is correct, anchor account predicts acceptability

Conclusions Directions for further inquiry: Crosslinguistic data

Conclusions Directions for further inquiry: Crosslinguistic data Bresnan and Dalrymple et al both consider crosslinguistic data (including German and Malayalam); this would help adjudicate between three treatments

Conclusions Directions for further inquiry: Crosslinguistic data Bresnan and Dalrymple et al both consider crosslinguistic data (including German and Malayalam); this would help adjudicate between three treatments Data from languages with less rigid word order would help in establishing (or rejecting) validity of a direct association principle

Conclusions Directions for further inquiry: Crosslinguistic data Bresnan and Dalrymple et al both consider crosslinguistic data (including German and Malayalam); this would help adjudicate between three treatments Data from languages with less rigid word order would help in establishing (or rejecting) validity of a direct association principle If anchor account is viable, could shed light on differences between the mental representations of adjuncts and arguments; also the status of objectivity w.r.t. the functional hierarchy

Conclusions Directions for further inquiry: Crosslinguistic data Bresnan and Dalrymple et al both consider crosslinguistic data (including German and Malayalam); this would help adjudicate between three treatments Data from languages with less rigid word order would help in establishing (or rejecting) validity of a direct association principle If anchor account is viable, could shed light on differences between the mental representations of adjuncts and arguments; also the status of objectivity w.r.t. the functional hierarchy Within English

Conclusions Directions for further inquiry: Crosslinguistic data Bresnan and Dalrymple et al both consider crosslinguistic data (including German and Malayalam); this would help adjudicate between three treatments Data from languages with less rigid word order would help in establishing (or rejecting) validity of a direct association principle If anchor account is viable, could shed light on differences between the mental representations of adjuncts and arguments; also the status of objectivity w.r.t. the functional hierarchy Within English Can the anchor account handle examples involving quantification, rather than wh-movement?

Conclusions Directions for further inquiry: Crosslinguistic data Bresnan and Dalrymple et al both consider crosslinguistic data (including German and Malayalam); this would help adjudicate between three treatments Data from languages with less rigid word order would help in establishing (or rejecting) validity of a direct association principle If anchor account is viable, could shed light on differences between the mental representations of adjuncts and arguments; also the status of objectivity w.r.t. the functional hierarchy Within English Can the anchor account handle examples involving quantification, rather than wh-movement? Other coreference phenomena (e.g. strong crossover)

Conclusions Directions for further inquiry: Crosslinguistic data Bresnan and Dalrymple et al both consider crosslinguistic data (including German and Malayalam); this would help adjudicate between three treatments Data from languages with less rigid word order would help in establishing (or rejecting) validity of a direct association principle If anchor account is viable, could shed light on differences between the mental representations of adjuncts and arguments; also the status of objectivity w.r.t. the functional hierarchy Within English Can the anchor account handle examples involving quantification, rather than wh-movement? Other coreference phenomena (e.g. strong crossover) Formalization (within LFG and other frameworks)

Synthetic data Following Dalrymple et al, I present data from hypothetical languages that would help to adjudicate between the three accounts. These are not exhaustive.

Synthetic data Following Dalrymple et al, I present data from hypothetical languages that would help to adjudicate between the three accounts. These are not exhaustive. Example (23) Only linear prominence applies; fixed SVO word order, wh-fronting: [[who i ] Op ] CoargOp, OBJ did [[his i ] Pro mother] CoargPro, SUBJ [see] Anch (t i )? Ungrammatical for Bresnan Grammatical for Dalrymple et al Anchor agrees with Bresnan (anchor and trace adjacent)

Synthetic data continued Example (24) Only linear prominence applies; fixed SOV word order, wh-fronting a. [[who i ] Op ] CoargOp, SUBJ (t i ) [[his i ] Pro mother] CoargPro, OBJ [saw] Anch? b. [[who i ] Op ] CoargOp, OBJ [[his i ] Pro mother] CoargPro, SUBJ (t i ) [saw] Anch? Extraction from subject position gives grammaticality from Bresnan and Dalrymple et al (24)a ungrammatical by anchor account; verb at the end of the sentence Extracting from object position gives ungrammaticality from Bresnan; others are unchanged

Synthetic data continued Example (25) Only linear prominence applies; fixed VSO word order, wh-fronting: [[who i ] Op ] CoargOp, OBJ [saw] Anch [[his i ] Pro mother] CoargPro, SUBJ (t i )? Grammatical for Dalrymple et al and anchor account (anchor occurs early) Ungrammatical for Bresnan

Synthetic data continued Example (26) Both linear and syntactic prominence must be satisfied; fixed SOV word order, wh-fronting: [[who i ] Op ] CoargOp, SUBJ (t i ) [[his i ] Pro mother] CoargPro, OBJ [saw] Anch? Grammatical for Dalrymple et al and Bresnan Word order constraints have anchor at the end of the sentence; anchor account predicts ungrammaticality

Synthetic data continued Lastly, suppose there is a language which requires only that one of the constraints be satisfied. If an example satisfies syntactic prominence here, all three accounts will predict grammaticality; thus it is only helpful to consider violations of syntactic prominence to adjudicate between accounts. Using linear prominence alone gives the same predictions as in (23)-(25), modulo word order.

Summary The anchor account apparently handles all data explained by Bresnan and Dalrymple et al

Summary The anchor account apparently handles all data explained by Bresnan and Dalrymple et al Fares better on unusual examples

Summary The anchor account apparently handles all data explained by Bresnan and Dalrymple et al Fares better on unusual examples Facts about coreference can be explained by direct association between extracted element and subcategorizer

Summary The anchor account apparently handles all data explained by Bresnan and Dalrymple et al Fares better on unusual examples Facts about coreference can be explained by direct association between extracted element and subcategorizer

Summary The anchor account apparently handles all data explained by Bresnan and Dalrymple et al Fares better on unusual examples Facts about coreference can be explained by direct association between extracted element and subcategorizer Conclusions: Traces are not strongly motivated by weak crossover

Summary The anchor account apparently handles all data explained by Bresnan and Dalrymple et al Fares better on unusual examples Facts about coreference can be explained by direct association between extracted element and subcategorizer Conclusions: Traces are not strongly motivated by weak crossover The association needs further exploration (particularly with respect to double objects, multiple gaps)

Summary The anchor account apparently handles all data explained by Bresnan and Dalrymple et al Fares better on unusual examples Facts about coreference can be explained by direct association between extracted element and subcategorizer Conclusions: Traces are not strongly motivated by weak crossover The association needs further exploration (particularly with respect to double objects, multiple gaps) This paper provides a starting point for a more formal theory of direct association

References 1. Bresnan 1995. Linear order, syntactic rank, and empty categories: on weak crossover. In Formal Issues in Lexical-Functional Grammar, Dalrymple, Kaplan, Maxwell & Zaenen (eds), 241-274. Stanford: CSLI. 2. Dalrymple, Kaplan & King 2001. Weak crossover and the absence of traces. In Proceedings of LFG01, Butt & King (eds). Stanford: CSLI. 3. Dalrymple & King 2013. Nested and crossing dependencies and the existence of traces. In From Quirky Case to Representing Space: Papers in Honor of Annie Zaenen, King & de Paiva (eds). Stanford: CSLI. 4. Dryer 1986. Primary objects, secondary objects, and antidative. Language 62: 808-845. 5. Engdahl 1983. Parasitic gaps. Linguistics & Philosophy 6: 5-34. 6. Kaplan & Bresnan 1982. Lexical-Functional Grammar: A formal system for grammatical representation. In Dalrymple, Kaplan, Maxwell & Zaenen (eds). 7. Kaplan & Zaenen (1989). Long-distance dependencies, constituent structure, and functional uncertainty. In Dalrymple, Kaplan, Maxwell & Zaenen (eds).

References continued 8. Keenan & Comrie 1977. Noun phrase accessibility and universal grammar. Linguistics Inquiry 8: 63-99. 9. Pickering & Barry 1991. Sentence processing without empty categories. Language & Cognitive Processes 6: 229-259. 10. Postal 1971. Cross-over Phenomena. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston. 11. Wasow 1972. Anaphoric relations in English. Ph.D., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.