Indeed and epistemic authority. Lauren McGarry, UCSC-Stanford Workshop on sentence types, January 29,

Similar documents
The Bulgarian Reportative as a Conventional Implicature Chronos 10. Dimka Atanassov University of Pennsylvania

Propositional Anaphora in English: The relationship between so and discourse

The Effect of Discourse Markers on the Speaking Production of EFL Students. Iman Moradimanesh

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

Declarative Questions

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

On rises and falls in interrogatives

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

AN INTRODUCTION (2 ND ED.) (LONDON, BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC PP. VI, 282)

ACTA PATTERNS OF STANCE TAKING NEGATIVE YES/NO INTERROGATIVES AND TAG QUESTIONS IN AMERICAN ENGLISH CONVERSATION UNIVERSITATIS OULUENSIS B 71

Part I. Figuring out how English works

Pragmatic Functions of Discourse Markers: A Review of Related Literature

Review in ICAME Journal, Volume 38, 2014, DOI: /icame

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

Rubric for Scoring English 1 Unit 1, Rhetorical Analysis

Focusing bound pronouns

Discrimination Complaints/Sexual Harassment

The Discourse Anaphoric Properties of Connectives

Specification and Evaluation of Machine Translation Toy Systems - Criteria for laboratory assignments

The Strong Minimalist Thesis and Bounded Optimality

Does Linguistic Communication Rest on Inference?

CLASS EXODUS. The alumni giving rate has dropped 50 percent over the last 20 years. How can you rethink your value to graduates?

TAG QUESTIONS" Department of Language and Literature - University of Birmingham

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

CEFR Overall Illustrative English Proficiency Scales

Realization of Textual Cohesion and Coherence in Business Letters through Presupposition 1

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

Lecture 9. The Semantic Typology of Indefinites

Replies to Greco and Turner

THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO. Department of Psychology

Journal of Pragmatics

Teaching Task Rewrite. Teaching Task: Rewrite the Teaching Task: What is the theme of the poem Mother to Son?

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

PHILOSOPHY & CULTURE Syllabus

Master s Thesis. An Agent-Based Platform for Dialogue Management

Phonological and Phonetic Representations: The Case of Neutralization

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

The Common European Framework of Reference for Languages p. 58 to p. 82

Possessive have and (have) got in New Zealand English Heidi Quinn, University of Canterbury, New Zealand

A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF MINNESOTA BY. Kaitlin Rose Johnson

Constraints on metalinguistic anaphora

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Modal Verbs for the Advice Move in Advice Columns

International Conference on Current Trends in ELT. Compliment Responses: A Comparative Study of Native English Speakers and Iranian L2 Speakers

A is an inde nite nominal pro-form that takes antecedents. ere have

Candidates must achieve a grade of at least C2 level in each examination in order to achieve the overall qualification at C2 Level.

Grammar Lesson Plan: Yes/No Questions with No Overt Auxiliary Verbs

A Case Study: News Classification Based on Term Frequency

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

Transitive meanings for intransitive verbs

To appear in The TESOL encyclopedia of ELT (Wiley-Blackwell) 1 RECASTING. Kazuya Saito. Birkbeck, University of London

Word Stress and Intonation: Introduction

The Pragmatics of Imperative and Declarative Pointing 1

Advances in Spoken Discourse Analysis

Foundations of Knowledge Representation in Cyc

Providing student writers with pre-text feedback

UC Santa Cruz Graduate Research Symposium 2016

LIMITED COMMON GROUND, UNLIMITED COMMUNICATIVE SUCCESS: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY INTO LINGUA RECEPTIVA USING ESTONIAN AND RUSSIAN

Author: Justyna Kowalczys Stowarzyszenie Angielski w Medycynie (PL) Feb 2015

Anticipation Guide William Faulkner s As I Lay Dying 2000 Modern Library Edition

A Comparative Study of Research Article Discussion Sections of Local and International Applied Linguistic Journals

Relevance Theory and the saying/implicating distinction *

L1 and L2 acquisition. Holger Diessel

MOODY SUBJUNCTIVE IN ROMANIAN *

Gricean Communication and Transmission of Thoughts

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

ANGLAIS LANGUE SECONDE

LQVSumm: A Corpus of Linguistic Quality Violations in Multi-Document Summarization

THE SHORT ANSWER: IMPLICATIONS FOR DIRECT COMPOSITIONALITY (AND VICE VERSA) Pauline Jacobson. Brown University

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

Revisiting the role of prosody in early language acquisition. Megha Sundara UCLA Phonetics Lab

Segmented Discourse Representation Theory. Dynamic Semantics with Discourse Structure

Writing for the AP U.S. History Exam

Practice Examination IREB

English Language and Applied Linguistics. Module Descriptions 2017/18

Common Core State Standards for English Language Arts

teaching issues 4 Fact sheet Generic skills Context The nature of generic skills

Making Sales Calls. Watertown High School, Watertown, Massachusetts. 1 hour, 4 5 days per week

IEP AMENDMENTS AND IEP CHANGES

Introduction to World Philosophy Syllabus Fall 2013 PHIL 2010 CRN: 89658

Strategic discourse comprehension

MYCIN. The MYCIN Task

Understanding the Relationship between Comprehension and Production

TU-E2090 Research Assignment in Operations Management and Services

An Analysis of Gender Differences in Minimal Responses in the conversations in the two TV-series Growing Pains and Boy Meets World

Monsters and the theoretical role of context

MA Linguistics Language and Communication

Learning Optimal Dialogue Strategies: A Case Study of a Spoken Dialogue Agent for

GERM 3040 GERMAN GRAMMAR AND COMPOSITION SPRING 2017

The BE + -ING form: Progressive aspect and metonymy

Tagged for Deletion: A Typological Approach to VP Ellipsis in Tag Questions

SETTING STANDARDS FOR CRITERION- REFERENCED MEASUREMENT

(3) Vocabulary insertion targets subtrees (4) The Superset Principle A vocabulary item A associated with the feature set F can replace a subtree X

3 Discourse Markers: Language, Meaning, and Context

Achievement Level Descriptors for American Literature and Composition

Language and Gender: How Question Tags Are Classified and Characterised in Current EFL Materials

Intension, Attitude, and Tense Annotation in a High-Fidelity Semantic Representation

An Approach to Polarity Sensitivity and Negative Concord by Lexical Underspecification

Heritage Korean Stage 6 Syllabus Preliminary and HSC Courses

Transcription:

1. Introduction Indeed and epistemic authority, lemcgarr@ucsc.edu UCSC-Stanford Workshop on sentence types, January 29, 2017 1 This paper discusses the discourse presuppositions of indeed as a response particle. Indeed can be used as a response to a wide range of sentence types, can convey a positive or negative response, and can reflect agreement or disagreement: (1) a. It s cold out. / It s cold out? / It s cold out, isn t it? b. Indeed (it is). (2) a. John is not the murderer. b. Indeed (he is not). c.?indeed he is! Manipulating the context (specifically, participants relative knowledge about the QUD) reveals part of indeed s basic meaning that underlies all of these responses. Roadmap: Hypothesis: Indeed presupposes that the speaker has equal or greater epistemic authority to commit to p relative to the addressee. Section 2 defines epistemic authority and the basis for my hypothesis Section 3 provides data on indeed and correct in various discourse contexts Section 4 discusses the implications of my analysis for indeed s co-occurrence with rising intonation. Seciton 5 discusses the open issue of the at-issue content of indeed and its function as a discourse anaphor. Section 6 concludes. 2. An appeal to authority Epistemic authority and evidential bias are prominent in literature on various types of declaratives and interrogatives. In the functional literature, we find some observations of how relative epistemic authority influences responses: (3) A: T s tsuh beautiful day out isn t it? B: Yeh it s jus gorgeous (Heritage & Raymond 2005) 1 Many thanks to Donka Farkas, Jim McCloskey, the Semantics Seminar, and all the students and professors present for my pre-290 presentations. All errors are my own. 1

A is downgrading her claim to authority by using a tag question. B agrees, but declines to assert primary rights [which A had intended to cede to her]. In other words, yeh marks B as having no more epistemic authority than A (Heritage & Raymond 2005). Following Heritage & Raymond 2005 as well as Northrup 2014, I am interested in how the relative authority of participants affects the felicity of indeed as a response. Relative epistemic authority: How qualified a participant is [based on his knowledge] to vouch for the truth of the proposition, compared to his interlocutors. (Northrup 2014) Cf. sourcehood and dependency, which describe absolute authority (i.e., whether a participant is qualified to commit to p, regardless of other participants knowledge or prior commitments) (Gunlogson 2008) Northrup argues that the Japanese discourse particle yo reflects maximal epistemic authority on the part of the speaker; that is, no participant has more authority than the speaker. The particle ne presupposes minimal speaker authority, i.e., that no participant has less authority than the speaker. Yone is used to express equal epistemic authority. Due to the availability of yone, yo is taken to implicate that the speaker has greater, not equal, authority relative to other participants. My hypothesis is that indeed, like yo, presupposes maximal (i.e., equal or greater) speaker authority. However, indeed differs from yo in that its potential meaning of equal epistemic authority is not ruled out by implicature. 3. Indeed and Correct 3.1. Responding to positive initiatives In order to better understand the function of indeed, I examine it alongside the intuitively similar response correct. Scenario: A woman brings her son to the doctor with a fever and a sore throat. She has researched the symptoms online and knows the child s classmates have had strep throat recently. She believes her son has strep throat, though she knows the symptoms have other potential causes. She calls the school to report the absence: (4) (SPEAKER > ADDRESSEE) 2 Teacher: He has strep./he has strep, doesn t he? Mother: Indeed./Correct. The mother has more epistemic authority than the teacher, and both indeed and correct are licensed. 2 Unless otherwise noted, SPEAKER refers to the participant who utters indeed/correct. 2

Indeed and correct are not valid in response to an addressee with greater epistemic authority: (5) (SPEAKER < ADDRESSEE) Doctor: (Having just run a test) He has strep throat. Mother: #Indeed./ #Correct. The mother s evidential base has not changed her addressee s has. This suggests that relative epistemic authority is at work. The infelicity in (5) is not due to the fact that indeed is relatively high-register. Indeed is permissible when the mother has equal or greater epistemic authority over the topic at hand. Correct requires that her epistemic authority be greater than her interlocutor s: (6) (SPEAKER = ADDRESSEE) Context: The woman measured her child s temperature at 100ºF using a reliable thermometer. The doctor does the same. Doctor: He has a fever. Mother: Indeed./ #Correct. (7) (SPEAKER > ADDRESSEE) Context: The doctor knows she is seeing a patient named James at 11:00. Doctor: This must be James. Mother: Indeed./ Correct. These data are summarized in (8) (8) Generalizations: SPEAKER = KNOWLEDGEABLE SPKR < ADD SPKR = ADD SPKR > ADD Indeed # Correct # # Indeed is licensed when the speaker has at least as much epistemic authority as their interlocutor, much like Japanese yo as described by Northrup (2014). Correct is licensed when the speaker has more epistemic authority. The following three sections examine the distribution of indeed and correct in response to other types of initiatives to further refine our understanding of their semantics. 3.2. Responding to negative initiatives: Agreeing We obtain the same generalizations regarding the acceptability of indeed and correct in agreeing responses to negative initiatives: 3

Scenario: A woman s son has been complaining of a stomachache (with no fever or sore throat). She measures his temperature with a reliable thermometer, and it is 98.6ºF. She researches his symptoms. Though strep has been going around, she feels confident in claiming that her son does not have strep (as a source). She calls his teacher and describes the symptoms: (9) (SPEAKER > ADDRESSEE) Teacher: He doesn t have strep. Mother: Indeed./ Correct. These responses are permitted in response to a less authoritative addressee. As in positive contexts, the mother cannot use these particles in response to a more authoritative participant: (10) (SPEAKER < ADDRESSEE) Doctor: (Having just run a test) He doesn t have strep throat. Mother: #Indeed./ #Correct. 3 When the topic under discussion is one for which both participants have equal authority, indeed is licensed. Correct still requires the speaker to have greater authority: (11) (SPEAKER = ADDRESSEE) Context: The woman measured her child s temperature at 98.6ºF using a reliable thermometer. The doctor does the same. Doctor: He doesn t have a fever. Mother: Indeed./ #Correct. (12) (SPEAKER > ADDRESSEE) Context: The doctor has treated this woman s other son, Michael, in the past. She can tell them apart reasonably well. Doctor: This is not Michael. Mother: Indeed./ Correct. Absolute polarity must not be included in their discourse presuppositions. But is relative polarity? 3.3. Responding to negative initiatives: Disagreeing The particles acceptability diverges in disagreeing contexts. Compare: (13) a. John is not the murderer. b. Indeed (he is not). 3 Tom Roberts has pointed out that indeed and correct may be felicitous here, if the mother feels that the test was unnecessary in light of her original suspicions; however, in such a scenario, the mother apparently believes herself to have better evidence than the test, and can use indeed or correct to present herself as the authority on the issue. 4

c.?indeed he is! d. He is indeed the murder! (14) a. John is not the murderer. b. Correct. (He is not). c. #Correct. He is! With what Krifka (2013) calls rejecting accent (boldface), indeed can be used to reject a negative initiative with a positive response. 4 Correct cannot. Correct requires the presupposition that the speaker agrees with the antecedent. Indeed requires no polarity-related presuppositions, as relative epistemic authority accounts for disagreement: You only correct someone when you believe that your knowledge on the matter is superior to your interlocutor s. Notes on disagreement with clause-initial indeed (13)b: Rejecting accent is required A prejacent is required These requirements do not derive from the semantics of indeed, but from the pragmatics of disagreement; disagreement is a marked discourse move, and therefore must be explicitly signaled (e.g., Farkas & Roelofsen s 2016, Farkas & Bruce 2010) 3.4. Responding to interrogatives Uttering a polar interrogative constitutes a request that the addressee decide some issue (Farkas & Bruce 2010); a non-trivial response is fully compatible with the respondent having greater epistemic authority. Any restrictions on indeed and correct in response to different interrogative types would indicate further presuppositions are needed. Each interrogative type and rising declarative shown in (15)-(18), licenses indeed. Correct, on the other hand, cannot be used in response to a standard polar interrogative (15): (15) POLAR INTERROGATIVE A: Is it cold out today? B: Indeed (it is)./ #(That s) correct. C: Is it not cold out today? D: Indeed (not)./ #(That s) correct. 4 It seems that clause-medial indeed cannot be used to disagree with a positive antecedent. This may be related to clause-medial indeed s syntactic position, or it may be that clause-medial indeed emphasizes positive polarity as part of its semantics. 5

(16) HIGH NEGATION POLAR INTERROGATIVE A: Isn t it cold out today? B: Indeed./ (That s) correct. C: Isn t it not cold out today? D: Indeed./ (That s) correct. (17) TAG QUESTION A: It s cold out today, isn t it? B: Indeed./ (That s) correct. C: It s not cold out today, is it? D: Indeed./ (That s) correct. (18) RISING DECLARATIVE A: It s cold out today? B: Indeed./ (That s) correct. C: It s not cold out today? D: Indeed./ (That s) correct. Polar questions do not express bias or commitment on the part of the asker, while RDs and other interrogative types do (Farkas & Roelofsen 2016, Gunlogson 2008, Malamud & Stevenson 2015). From this, we can conclude that correct requires that the addressee has expressed bias or commitment to the highlighted possibility. Indeed does not require bias, but it does rely on the presence of a single highlighted response on the table (Farkas & Bruce 2010): (19) ALTERNATIVE POLAR INTERROGATIVE A: Is it cold out today, or not? B: #Indeed./ #(That s) correct. Summary Indeed commits the speaker to the antecedent or its complement. If the latter, there must be an overt prejacent. Indeed presupposes that: The speaker has maximal (equal or greater) epistemic authority to commit to p relative to the addressee There is a single highlighted proposition on the table. Correct commits the speaker to the antecedent. It presupposes that: The speaker has greater epistemic authority to commit to p than the addressee There is a single highlighted proposition on the table. The addressee has already expressed bias or commitment toward p. 6

4. Predictions about rising intonation Rising intonation on a declarative designates the hearer as an implicit authority (i.e., as being the projected source for p or p). I adopt Farkas and Roelofsen s (2016) analysis of rising declaratives: Speakers do not commit to p, but signal at most low credence for p relative to p. In most contexts, RDs cede epistemic authority to the addressee; he is expected to commit to one of the possibilities on the table as a source. In some contexts (e.g., surprise, instruction, snideness), an RD signaling minimal credence for p is meant to convey endorsement of p, and emphasizes the speaker s greater epistemic authority on p v p: (20) Context: Mother asks her child to set the table and he does a particularly bad job of it but appears to consider the chore finished. Mother: This table is set? Where are the glasses? Where are the napkins? Prediction: If indeed is indeed a marker of equal or greater epistemic authority, we would predict it to be incompatible with rising intonation in typical RD contexts, but licensed in snide/surprise contexts. This prediction is borne out, as shown in the typical (21) 5 and surprise (22) contexts below: (21) Context: A substitute teacher is taking attendance, and consults a student because she seems to know everyone in the class. Teacher: That s James over there? / Is that James over there? Student (unsure): #Indeed? / Yes? / Yeah? (22) A: One of the crimes was embezzlement, but that s the lesser offense. B: Indeed? Embezzlement is quite serious. (COCA) These data support the claim that indeed presupposes maximal speaker authority. 5. Open questions: Indeed s relationship to antecedents Northrup s authority-based analysis of yo has been useful in determining the presuppositions of indeed, but has not shed light on its function as a discourse anaphor or its at-issue contribution. Farkas & Bruce 2010, Farkas and Roelofsen 2016: Polarity particles (yes and no) reflect the absolute and relative polarity of their prejacents. The prejacents are anaphoric to a highlighted (i.e., explicitly stated) possibility p from the immediately preceding context. 5 COCA contains several tokens of bare indeed as a rising declarative in response to speaker-new information, without asserting authority or challenging that information. However, these are all from fantasy or historical fiction novels, in which authors employ an artificially archaic dialect. We should not draw any conclusions based on these data. 7

Indeed resembles yes and no: Its contribution p is derived from immediately preceding context based on the highlighting of a single proposition, and it is often accompanied by a prejacent: (23) A: Is it cold out today? B: Indeed it is. Indeed s relationship to its prejacent is quite different from yes or no s, as the prejacent may be positive or negative, and may agree or disagree with the antecedent. This requires further investigation. Indeed has an additional responsive function as a speech act anaphor: (24) A: Why would John do such a thing? B: Why indeed. We may never know his motives. (25) Context: A couple is having a serious argument. B acts as though he is leaving, but is continuing to argue. A: So are you staying or going? B: Indeed! 6 This use of indeed seems to carry the same discourse presuppositions with regard to relative epistemic authority, but further study is needed to determine whether there are further limitations on the distribution of indeed as a speech act anaphor. 6. Conclusion The concept of relative epistemic authority developed in the functional literature and by Northrup (2014) is critical to understanding the distribution of certain response particles in English. Indeed presupposes that the speaker has equal or greater epistemic authority relative to the addressee with respect to some proposition p or some speech act, which the addressee has highlighted in the preceding context. Correct presupposes greater epistemic authority on the part of the speaker, and that the speaker is agreeing with some proposition toward which the hearer has expressed bias. Going forward, this project will further explore issues of discourse anaphora and the interaction between a non-polar response particle and its prejacent. 7. References Davies, 2008. Contemporary Corpus of American English. Farkas, D. and Bruce, K. (2010). On reacting to assertions and polar questions. Journal of Semantics 27: 81-118. 6 Thanks to Sandy Chung for thinking of this example. 8

Farkas, D. F. and Roelofsen, F. (2016). Division of labor in the interpretation of declaratives and interrogatives. Accepted subject to minor revisions, Journal of Semantics. Gunlogson, C. (2008). A question of commitment. Belgian Journal of Linguistics, 22, 101 136. Heritage, J. and Raymond, G.T. (2005). The terms of agreement: Indexing epistemic authority and subordination in talk-in-interaciton. Social Psychology Quarterly, 68(1), 15-38. Krifka, M. (2013). Response particles as propositional anaphors. In Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT 23), pages 1 18. Malamud, S. and Stephenson, T. (2015). Three ways to avoid commitments: Declarative force modifiers in the conversational scoreboard. Journal of Semantics, 32, 275 311. Northrup, O. (2014). Grounds for Commitment. Ph.D. thesis, UCSC. 9