On Nominal Complements and Adjuncts

Similar documents
Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Theoretical Syntax Winter Answers to practice problems

Argument structure and theta roles

Pseudo-Passives as Adjectival Passives

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

Derivational: Inflectional: In a fit of rage the soldiers attacked them both that week, but lost the fight.

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

LING 329 : MORPHOLOGY

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

Emmaus Lutheran School English Language Arts Curriculum

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

Context Free Grammars. Many slides from Michael Collins

Hindi-Urdu Phrase Structure Annotation

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

Writing a composition

ELD CELDT 5 EDGE Level C Curriculum Guide LANGUAGE DEVELOPMENT VOCABULARY COMMON WRITING PROJECT. ToolKit

BULATS A2 WORDLIST 2

ENGBG1 ENGBL1 Campus Linguistics. Meeting 2. Chapter 7 (Morphology) and chapter 9 (Syntax) Pia Sundqvist

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Inleiding Taalkunde. Docent: Paola Monachesi. Blok 4, 2001/ Syntax 2. 2 Phrases and constituent structure 2. 3 A minigrammar of Italian 3

Words come in categories

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

Derivational and Inflectional Morphemes in Pak-Pak Language

Opportunities for Writing Title Key Stage 1 Key Stage 2 Narrative

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Chapter 9 Banked gap-filling

Parallel Evaluation in Stratal OT * Adam Baker University of Arizona

Citation for published version (APA): Veenstra, M. J. A. (1998). Formalizing the minimalist program Groningen: s.n.

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

California Department of Education English Language Development Standards for Grade 8

Dear Teacher: Welcome to Reading Rods! Reading Rods offer many outstanding features! Read on to discover how to put Reading Rods to work today!

Parsing of part-of-speech tagged Assamese Texts

Word Stress and Intonation: Introduction

1 st Quarter (September, October, November) August/September Strand Topic Standard Notes Reading for Literature

1/20 idea. We ll spend an extra hour on 1/21. based on assigned readings. so you ll be ready to discuss them in class

Som and Optimality Theory

First Grade Curriculum Highlights: In alignment with the Common Core Standards

Language Acquisition by Identical vs. Fraternal SLI Twins * Karin Stromswold & Jay I. Rifkin

Grammars & Parsing, Part 1:

Today we examine the distribution of infinitival clauses, which can be

Chapter 3: Semi-lexical categories. nor truly functional. As Corver and van Riemsdijk rightly point out, There is more

Developing Grammar in Context

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

Advanced Grammar in Use

Guidelines for Writing an Internship Report

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

The optimal placement of up and ab A comparison 1

Noun incorporation in Sora: A case for incorporation as morphological merger TLS: 19 February Introduction.

Construction Grammar. University of Jena.

Aspectual Classes of Verb Phrases

Copyright 2017 DataWORKS Educational Research. All rights reserved.

Chapter 4: Valence & Agreement CSLI Publications

The Structure of Relative Clauses in Maay Maay By Elly Zimmer

Adjectives tell you more about a noun (for example: the red dress ).

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

The redundancy of lexical categories

Loughton School s curriculum evening. 28 th February 2017

Phenomena of gender attraction in Polish *

CORPUS ANALYSIS CORPUS ANALYSIS QUANTITATIVE ANALYSIS

Update on Soar-based language processing

AN ANALYSIS OF GRAMMTICAL ERRORS MADE BY THE SECOND YEAR STUDENTS OF SMAN 5 PADANG IN WRITING PAST EXPERIENCES

Introduction to Questionnaire Design

Notes on The Sciences of the Artificial Adapted from a shorter document written for course (Deciding What to Design) 1

On the Notion Determiner

Dependency, licensing and the nature of grammatical relations *

What the National Curriculum requires in reading at Y5 and Y6

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Long-distance wh-movement. Long distance wh-movement. Islands. Islands. Locality. NP Sea. NP Sea

An Interactive Intelligent Language Tutor Over The Internet

Conteúdos de inglês para o primeiro bimestre. Turma 21. Turma 31. Turma 41

Natural Language Processing. George Konidaris

UKLO Round Advanced solutions and marking schemes. 6 The long and short of English verbs [15 marks]

Syntax Parsing 1. Grammars and parsing 2. Top-down and bottom-up parsing 3. Chart parsers 4. Bottom-up chart parsing 5. The Earley Algorithm

SOME MINIMAL NOTES ON MINIMALISM *

L1 and L2 acquisition. Holger Diessel

Objectives. Chapter 2: The Representation of Knowledge. Expert Systems: Principles and Programming, Fourth Edition

THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & SOCIAL STUDIES

Common Core ENGLISH GRAMMAR & Mechanics. Worksheet Generator Standard Descriptions. Grade 2

Control and Boundedness

Thornhill Primary School - Grammar coverage Year 1-6

CHILDREN S POSSESSIVE STRUCTURES: A CASE STUDY 1. Andrew Radford and Joseph Galasso, University of Essex

A Usage-Based Approach to Recursion in Sentence Processing

Books Effective Literacy Y5-8 Learning Through Talk Y4-8 Switch onto Spelling Spelling Under Scrutiny

11/29/2010. Statistical Parsing. Statistical Parsing. Simple PCFG for ATIS English. Syntactic Disambiguation

A Computational Evaluation of Case-Assignment Algorithms

Nancy Hennessy M.Ed. 1

The Role of the Head in the Interpretation of English Deverbal Compounds

Beyond constructions:

Improved Effects of Word-Retrieval Treatments Subsequent to Addition of the Orthographic Form

Informatics 2A: Language Complexity and the. Inf2A: Chomsky Hierarchy

Character Stream Parsing of Mixed-lingual Text

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

The presence of interpretable but ungrammatical sentences corresponds to mismatches between interpretive and productive parsing.

LIN 6520 Syntax 2 T 5-6, Th 6 CBD 234

a) analyse sentences, so you know what s going on and how to use that information to help you find the answer.

NAME: East Carolina University PSYC Developmental Psychology Dr. Eppler & Dr. Ironsmith

Part I. Figuring out how English works

Transcription:

1 Secondary Complements On ominal Complements and Adjuncts ancy Hedberg and Richard C. DeArmond Simon Fraser University In DeArmond and Hedberg (1998) we showed there exists a distinction between primary and secondary complements of the verb; these complements are distinct from adjuncts. In this paper we will show that there is a similar distinction between primary and secondary complements of nouns. Adjuncts are modifiers of the constituent to which they are adjoined, while complements are arguments of a lexical head. Primary complements are arguments of the integral meaning of the head. Secondary complements are arguments assigned by a lexical feature incorporated into the head. For example the agent is an argument of CAUSE as in (1b): (1) a. The window broke. BREAK <patient> (semelfactive) b. Leslie broke the window. BREAK+CAUSE <<patient> agent> (accomplishment) Logically in (1b), the agent Leslie receives its theta role from CAUSE, which underlies the transitive verb. When the intransitive verb incorporates CAUSE forming the transitive verb, the verb is then seen as taking the theta role agent as in (1b), instrument as in (2a), and benefactive as in (2c) through the lexical feature CAUSE as in (2) (2) a. Leslie broke the window with a rock. (instrument) b. *The window broke with a rock. c. Leslie broke the window for her brother. (benefactive) d. *The window broke for her brother. These arguments, which we call secondary complements, have somewhat different properties from primary complements. This distinction was the topic of our 1998 paper. This differentiation, we claim, is due to the fact that the agent, instrument, and benefactive are not assigned by the integral meaning of such lexical features as BREAK. They are assigned by the integral meaning of such lexical features as CAUSE. In noun phrases post-nominal adjuncts may occur in the form of a PP. If the PP can be replaced with a relative clause with no change in lexical meaning, they are adjuncts as in (3): (3) a. The book on the table is red. b. The book which is on the table is red. Complements cannot be replaced with a relative clause with no change in lexical meaning as in (4b): April 6, 2004 1 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm

(4) a. The basket of tomatoes looks appetizing. b. *The basket which is of tomatoes looks appetizing. There are other tests for post-nominal adjuncts, but each has a limited range. The pseudo-cleft test and other tests differentiate primary and secondary complements of the verb. When break is an accomplishment verb, an instrument is possible. Only the instrument, a secondary complement, can occur in the post-auxiliary-verb position in a pseudo-cleft construction as in (5a): (5) a. What Leslie did with a hammer is break the window. b. *What Leslie did the window is break with a hammer. We return to this topic below. These and other related tests function as good tests for the distinction between primary and secondary complements in the verb. However, the pseudo-cleft test and related tests such as P-preposing are not available for noun phrases. 1.1 Prenominal Complement Test In Ps, however, instruments, which we claim are secondary complements, cannot occur in prenominal position unlike primary complements in compounds of the following sort as in (6): (6) a. Hunting of bears with pistols is illegal. b. Bear hunting with pistols is illegal. c. *Pistol hunting (of bears) is illegal. d. *Pistol bear hunting is illegal. e. **Bear pistol hunting is illegal. Bears is the theme and pistols is the instrument. Example (6e) seems worse that either (6c) or (6d). This may be because there is only one prenominal position for complements. The same holds true for agents and benefactives, which we have claimed are also secondary complements. The examples in (7) illustrate agents: (7) a. *Hunter shooting of bears (with pistols) is illegal. b. (*) Hunter shooting is illegal. (7a) is unacceptable because hunter can be interpreted only as an agent; it cannot be interpreted as a goal. (7b) is acceptable if hunter is the goal, but not if it is an agent. The examples in (8) illustrate benefactives: (8) a. The hunter shot a bear for a buddy. b. The shooting of a bear for a buddy is disgusting. c. *The buddy shooting of a bear by the hunter is disgusting. Purpose clauses are also secondary complements as in (9): April 6, 2004 2 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm

(9) a. The hunter shot a bear for $50. b. The shooting of a bear for $50 by the hunter is not condoned. c. (*)The $50 shooting of a bear by the hunter is not condoned. ote that (9c) is acceptable if $50 refers to the cost of the shooting, not the purpose. In this case $50 is an adjunct as in (10): (10) The shooting of the bear by the hunter, which was for $50, was not condoned. However, adjuncts may occur before the prenominal complement position as in (11): (11) a. The student of physics at McGill b. The McGill student of physics c. The McGill physics student. Example (11c) is interesting, since it shows both a prenominal adjunct position and the prenominal complement position. The complement must be closer to the head; the same ordering constraint holds elsewhere as in (12): (12) a. *The physics McGill student b. The MIT English teacher c. (*)The English MIT teacher. (12c) is acceptable if English is a modifier of teacher--the teacher who is English, but it is not acceptable if English is an complement of teacher--the subject that he teaches. 1.2 Predicate Separation Test Another test for secondary complements is the predicate separation test. 1 In the predicate separation test an adjunct or a secondary complement may occur in the predicate position of a copular construction as in (13) and (14): (13) a. The book on the table is green. (PP = adjunct) b. The book is on the table. (14) a. The destruction of the city with bombs was deplorable. b. The destruction of the city was with bombs. (PP = secondary complement) A primary complement cannot occur in the predicate position as in (15): (15) *The destruction with bombs was of the city. 1. For this test and following test, we are grateful to athalie Schapansky who suggested them. April 6, 2004 3 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm

Thus, the predicate separation test differentiates primary and secondary arguments, but it does not differentiate secondary arguments from adjuncts. 1.3 Left Dislocation Test A left dislocated P may be coindexed with a primary or a secondary complement, but it is not easily coindexed with an adjunct. If the preposition head of the adjunct is retained the result is ungrammatical. If the preposition plus the resumptive pronoun is replaced with there, then, the result is questionable. If the adjunct is a manner adjunct, left dislocation is not possible as in (16): (16) a. As for the floor, John s painting it with the new brush in the morning failed to impress Mary. b. As for the new brush, John s painting the floor with it failed to impress Mary. c. As for the morning, John s painting the floor with the new brush (*in it) (??then) failed to impress Mary. d. As for the new house, John s painting the floor with the new brush (*in it) (??there) failed to impress Mary. e. *As for ease, John s painting the floor with the new brush with it failed to impress Mary. 1.4 The possessive P Test Agents and primary complements of the open class of verbs may be advanced to the determiner position of the noun phrase, but secondary complements and adjuncts may not as in (17c), (17d), and (18c): (17) a. The opening of the door with a pick at night startled Sam. b. The door s opening with a pick at night startled Sam. c. *A pick s opening of the door at night startled Sam. d. *ight s opening of the door with a pick startled Sam. (18) a. The destruction of the city with a bomb by the enemy infuriated Milosevich. b. The city s destruction with a bomb by the enemy infuriated Milosevich. c. *The bomb s destruction of the city by the enemy infuriated Milosevich. However, if the secondary complement may be advanced to the subject position in the verbal form, the same argument may be advanced to the determiner position in the Pas in (19): (19) a. The bomb destroyed the city (*by the enemy). b. The bomb s destruction of the city infuriated Milosevich. April 6, 2004 4 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm

1.5 Word order There is a constraint on word order secondary complements must follow primary complements as in (20): (20) a. The hunting of bears with a rifle b. *The hunting with a rifle of bears Without the evidence found in the prenominal complement position, word order would not provide a convincing argument for secondary complements. Many factors influence word order, for example: the relative weight of constituents (as in heavy P-shift), new and old information and similar factors, arbitrary left and right branching. However, word order does support the secondary complement hypothesis given the prenominal argument test and other tests that more strongly support it. Primary complements are closer to their heads than secondary complements in fixed word order languages. 1.6 Recursion When a PP is appended to a noun phrase, the PP can only be an adjunct. Unlike adjuncts primary and secondary complements cannot be iteratively appended to noun phrase complements as in (21b): (21) a. The writing of a letter with a quill on the table in the front room in our summer house is inspiring. b. *The writing of a letter with a quill with a pen in our summer house is inspiring. With a pen is a PP that is an argument of the verb and cannot be adjoined to another complement. In the intended reading of (21b), with a pen is adjoined to with a quill. As (21a) shows, PPs may be iteratively adjoined to adjuncts. This restriction on appending PPs to an argument is a general property of complements, and provides evidence that secondary complements are complements and not adjuncts. ote also that there is another reading of (21b), where with a pen could be analyzed as a second instrument. In this case the Theta-Criterion is violated, where two Ps are assigned to the same theta-position instrument. Such is possible only under terms of conjunction as in (22): (22) The writing of a letter with a quill or with a pen by Ken in our summer house is inspiring. Secondary complements either share properties with primary complements or they share properties with adjuncts as the tests above show. They show that primary complements are differentiated from secondary complements and adjuncts in that they are part of the integral meaning of the verb, or adjuncts are distinct from primary and secondary complements in that they are not part of the meaning of the verb at all. In the next section we discuss the theory of secondary complements in noun phrases. April 6, 2004 5 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm

2 Theoretical Concerns Primary complements are part of the integral meaning of a lexical constituent they are arguments of the constituent. Certain constituents are composed, arguably, of two or more lexical features or a bundle of lexical features. Let us start with accomplishment verbs. Accomplishment verbs imply an agent. Underlying accomplishment verbs may be a verb marking a state, an activity, or semelfactiveness. Break is basically a semelfactive verb as in (23): (23) The dish broke! In its basic meaning it refers to a sudden event. There are several sub-meanings that are not semelfactive. We will not consider them here. It takes one argument, whose argument structure we represent as as in (24): (24) BREAK <patient> erbs such as break with the structure given in (24) we will call primary verbs: (25) Primary erb A primary verb is a verb that cannot be decomposed into a set of lexical features whose arguments are referentially distinct. For example, the intransitive verb break is primary. Break may be decomposed into three subevents (see Pustejovsky 1995): an initial state, a momentary action referring to the event of breaking, and the final state. In all three subevents, the argument of each sub-predicate is the same. In the following example the common argument window: is (26) a. STATE <theme: window> b. SEMELF. ACTIO <patient: window> c. STATE <theme: window> When break combines with CAUSE to form the transitive verb BREAK, the result is the transitive verb break, homophonous with but distinct from the intransitive verb. The structure and incorporation of CAUSE into BREAK is shown in (27) April 6, 2004 6 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm

(27) phrase operator CAUSE phrase predicate semelfative action BREAK CAUSE break object patient DISH (the) dish object agent WAITER (the) waiter The derived verb is not a primary (or integral) verb. It is composed in part of BREAK <patient> and CAUSE <agent>. ote that CAUSE takes two arguments: agent, and the phrase containing BREAK. We take the view here that CAUSE is incorporated into the primary lexical item BREAK a process that occurs in the lexicon before the lexical meaning is assigned. 3 ominals 3.1 Monadic ominals ouns can be divided into various classes. The first is object, such as bears in (20). We define object as a noun that assigns no arguments. Objects include tangible and intangible things such as dish, button, dirt, water, sea, air and so forth. There are several classes of nouns that assign arguments. One such class includes containers: glass, bottle, cup, can, vase, barrel, and so forth as in (28): (28) a. John drank a cup of coffee. b. Mary bought a barrel of oil. We consider containers to be lexical quantifiers. For example cup in (28a) where cup is referring to the container of the coffee. Most if not all containers are also objects as in (29): (29) a. John dropped and broke the cup(*of coffee). b. That factory makes barrels(*of oil). As objects, they do not take arguments as shown immediately above. We propose that containers have a structure similar to that in (30) representing cup as in (30): April 6, 2004 7 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm

(30) () CUP object COTAIER <theme> cup The figure in (30) indicates that the container cup is derived from the object cup, and that container assigns an argument, theme, which in (28) are of coffee, and of oil, respectively. 2 Containers are nouns like their underlying objects indicated here by placing the category in parentheses. The lexical item CUP [COTAIER] is spelled out as the grapheme cup, written outside of the outer brackets. ext there are gerundials, which have been discussed above. Gerundials are pure nouns that are derived from verbs including the argument structure of the underlying verb. First let us start with the intransitive gerundial breaking. The use of a singular object seems rather odd, but not ungrammatical as in (31): (31)?The breaking of the dish was rather sudden. The use with a plural object seems better as in (32): (32) The breaking of the dishes was unexpected. Putting aside the question of the number feature of the object, a partial lexical entry for the underlying verb is as in (33): (33) BREAK predicate activity <patient > the lexical entry for the intransitive gerundial incorporates the above verb as in (34): 2. See Pustejovsky (1995) for a discussion of the derivations of this type. April 6, 2004 8 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm

(34) action BREAK predicate activity <patient > Action here refers to the gerundial. Action does not add an argument to the underlying lexical feature, which is the activity BREAK. The morphology of gerundials determines that the form splits into a verbal stem (BREAK) and the derivational suffix -ing marking action and forming a nominal projection. The activity is spelled out as break and the action as ing as in (35): (35) BREAK predicate activity <patient > break action ing In constructions of this sort, the external feature determines the category of the item, which is. In the syntax the argument of the feature activity is spelled out as a phrasal complement of the verb. In derivations of the above type the argument is spelled out in a similar way. However, the feature blocks Case assignment of the direct object by the verb as in (36): April 6, 2004 9 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm

(36) P P BREAK predicate activity <patient > action D the P dishes break ing Such diagrams as (35), (36), and so forth, are usually written without the lexical features represented in caps here; BREAK is spelled out as break and as -ing. Depending on one s analysis, the preposition of is inserted to assign Case to the direct object, or the preposition may be viewed as K, for Case: Similarly, depending on one s analysis, P may be viewed as DP. We will use P here as in (37): (37) P PP BREAK predicate activity <patient > break action ing P of D the P P dishes 3.2 Polyadic ominals Transitive gerundials are formed from transitive verbs with relative ease as in (38): (38) a. The hunter shot a bear. b. The shooting of a bear by the hunter was cruel. April 6, 2004 10 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm

Intransitive gerundials are formed from intransitive verbs as shown in (43a) and (44a) where the stem of the intransitive verb is phonologically distinct from the stem of the transitive verb as in (38) and (39): (39) a. The rising of goats into the air was awesome. b. The raising of goats is not much fun. (40) a. The falling of the trees during the storm was frightening. b. The felling of the trees by the woodsmen must be stopped. A transitive verb, we claim, must underlie a transitive gerundial for the following reason. The lexical feature CAUSE can only take an event as an argument. We know no examples of causative nouns that are not derived from verbs. It would be more difficult to account for how an abstract lexical feature when adjoined to a derived stem such as RISE+IG would affect the inner stem morpheme RISE. Usually, only external affixes can be affected by a morphophonemic change. Suppose, for example, that raising were derived from rising. The feature ACTIO would first be incorporated into RISE, and then CAUSE would be incorporated into RISE[ACTIO] as in (41): (41) CAUSE ACTIO RISE Here, CAUSE would have to have an affect on RISE, which is embedded two levels down to determine the verb raise. Given the pattern of morphophonemic alternations this is an unexpected and an undesirable result. However, if the transitive gerundial is derived from the transitive verb, which is in turn derived from the intransitive verb, this unexpected alternation does not arise as in (42): (42) ACTIO CAUSE RISE April 6, 2004 11 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm

In (42) CAUSE has an affect on its own argument, which is one level down, creating the stem raise. This is the desired effect. In conclusion of this section we claim that gerundials are directly derived from verbs. 4 Prenominal Position Following Radford (1988:198ff) the first pre-nominal position may be an argument position. on-arguments must precede argument positions before the noun as in (43): (43) a. The shooting of fast bears is rarely acceptable. b. Fast bear shooting is rarely acceptable. c. The fast shooting of bears is rarely acceptable. d. *Bear fast shooting is rarely acceptable. (43d) is ungrammatical because the argument bear does not occur in the immediate prenominal position. (43b) is ambiguous. Fast is modifying either bear or shooting. If the first prenominal position is a complement, then it is an A-position. The question arises is whether the prenominal complement position is restricted, and if so to what? The prenominal complement position appears to be restricted to generic Ps. A definite P is not permitted in that position as in (44b) and (44c): (44) a. The shooting of that bear was totally uncalled for. b. *The that bear shooting was totally uncalled for. c. (*)That bear shooting was totally uncalled for. (44c) is ambiguous. (44c) is ungrammatical in the reading where that is modifying bear, but it is grammatical in the reading where that is modifying the gerund. It seems that only lexical modifiers may modify nouns in the prenominal complement position, operators including quantifiers may not modify nouns here: as shown in (45): (45) a. The shooting of three bears is always illegal. b. *(The) three bear shooting is always illegal. c. *All bears shooting is always illegal. d. *Some bears shooting is always illegal. If the noun takes a complement neither the noun nor the complement may occur in the prenominal position of the gerundial as in (46): April 6, 2004 12 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm

(46) a. The poisoning of gaggles of geese is deplorable. b. *Gaggles of geese poisoning is deplorable. c. Goose poisoning is deplorable. d. *Goose poisoning of gaggles of is deplorable. e. *Gaggle poisoning of of geese is deplorable. As these examples in (46) show, the prenominal position is highly restricted as to what may be placed there. 5 Conclusion In this paper we have shown that adjuncts, secondary complements, and primary complements can be distinguished in the P as well as in the P. We are especially interested in the distinction between primary and secondary complements. We have given a number of syntactic tests to distinguish them. And also a couple of syntactic tests to distinguish adjuncts from the other two. In the remaininder of the paper we have discusdsed a variety of more theoretical concerns including yhe analysis of container nouns, gerundials, and nominal compounds. Thus, the prenominal position is limited to two classes: (1) a primary complement a generic intransitive lexical noun complement of the head noun and (2) a lexical modifier of the complement noun. 6 Bibliography DeArmond, Richard C. and ancy Hedberg. (1998). Proceedings of the Canadian Linguistic Associatioon Annjula Conference, Cahiers Linguistiques d Ottawa. Pustejovsky, James. (1995). The Generative Lexicon. Cambridge: MIT Press. April 6, 2004 13 File: On_nominal_comp_adjnt.fm