On the force of V2 declaratives*

Similar documents
Proof Theory for Syntacticians

The Discourse Effects of the Indefinite Demonstrative dieser in German

Lecture 9. The Semantic Typology of Indefinites

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Theoretical Syntax Winter Answers to practice problems

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

THE SOME INDEFINITES

Agree or Move? On Partial Control Anna Snarska, Adam Mickiewicz University

Applying Speaking Criteria. For use from November 2010 GERMAN BREAKTHROUGH PAGRB01

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

Writing a composition

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

Context-Sensitive Bidirectional OT: a New Approach to Russian Aspect

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

Annotation Projection for Discourse Connectives

The Bulgarian Reportative as a Conventional Implicature Chronos 10. Dimka Atanassov University of Pennsylvania

EAGLE: an Error-Annotated Corpus of Beginning Learner German

Some Principles of Automated Natural Language Information Extraction

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

A New Semantics for Number

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

Reading Grammar Section and Lesson Writing Chapter and Lesson Identify a purpose for reading W1-LO; W2- LO; W3- LO; W4- LO; W5-

California Department of Education English Language Development Standards for Grade 8

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

The presence of interpretable but ungrammatical sentences corresponds to mismatches between interpretive and productive parsing.

Monsters and the theoretical role of context

Focusing bound pronouns

Participate in expanded conversations and respond appropriately to a variety of conversational prompts

The Verbmobil Semantic Database. Humboldt{Univ. zu Berlin. Computerlinguistik. Abstract

Possessive have and (have) got in New Zealand English Heidi Quinn, University of Canterbury, New Zealand

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

5. UPPER INTERMEDIATE

A Version Space Approach to Learning Context-free Grammars

Objectives. Chapter 2: The Representation of Knowledge. Expert Systems: Principles and Programming, Fourth Edition

Replies to Greco and Turner

An Approach to Polarity Sensitivity and Negative Concord by Lexical Underspecification

Rule-based Expert Systems

A comment on the topic of topic comment

Susanne J. Jekat

Welcome to the Purdue OWL. Where do I begin? General Strategies. Personalizing Proofreading

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

CAAP. Content Analysis Report. Sample College. Institution Code: 9011 Institution Type: 4-Year Subgroup: none Test Date: Spring 2011

SOME MINIMAL NOTES ON MINIMALISM *

Segmented Discourse Representation Theory. Dynamic Semantics with Discourse Structure

On rises and falls in interrogatives

Mandarin Lexical Tone Recognition: The Gating Paradigm

Dreistadt: A language enabled MOO for language learning

LIN 6520 Syntax 2 T 5-6, Th 6 CBD 234

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Korean ECM Constructions and Cyclic Linearization

THE SHORT ANSWER: IMPLICATIONS FOR DIRECT COMPOSITIONALITY (AND VICE VERSA) Pauline Jacobson. Brown University

Argument structure and theta roles

Declarative Questions

Loughton School s curriculum evening. 28 th February 2017

MYCIN. The MYCIN Task

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

Intervention in Tough Constructions * Jeremy Hartman. Massachusetts Institute of Technology

(Re)Formalizing the Imperative Sentence Type. David Medeiros,

Propositional Anaphora in English: The relationship between so and discourse

GERM 3040 GERMAN GRAMMAR AND COMPOSITION SPRING 2017

Word Stress and Intonation: Introduction

Derivations (MP) and Evaluations (OT) *

ENGBG1 ENGBL1 Campus Linguistics. Meeting 2. Chapter 7 (Morphology) and chapter 9 (Syntax) Pia Sundqvist

Som and Optimality Theory

Negative Indefinites in Dutch and German. Doris Penka & Hedde Zeijlstra {d.penka

Discourse markers and grammaticalization

Taught Throughout the Year Foundational Skills Reading Writing Language RF.1.2 Demonstrate understanding of spoken words,

Specification and Evaluation of Machine Translation Toy Systems - Criteria for laboratory assignments

Number Sentences and Specificational Sentences

The Discourse Anaphoric Properties of Connectives

...WE CAN DO BETTER TIN-dag 2012, February 4, 2012

The Effect of Discourse Markers on the Speaking Production of EFL Students. Iman Moradimanesh

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

Transitive meanings for intransitive verbs

Phenomena of gender attraction in Polish *

1 st Quarter (September, October, November) August/September Strand Topic Standard Notes Reading for Literature

Pseudo-Passives as Adjectival Passives

Providing student writers with pre-text feedback

Dissertation Summaries. The Acquisition of Aspect and Motion Verbs in the Native Language (Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, 2014)

The Structure of Multiple Complements to V

On the distribution of German discourse particles across types of questions

Semantic Inference at the Lexical-Syntactic Level for Textual Entailment Recognition

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Long-distance wh-movement. Long distance wh-movement. Islands. Islands. Locality. NP Sea. NP Sea

5 Minimalism and Optimality Theory

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

Statewide Framework Document for:

First Grade Curriculum Highlights: In alignment with the Common Core Standards

Specifying Logic Programs in Controlled Natural Language

Part I. Figuring out how English works

AGENDA LEARNING THEORIES LEARNING THEORIES. Advanced Learning Theories 2/22/2016

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

Strategic discourse comprehension

Language Acquisition Chart

On the Notion Determiner

ELD CELDT 5 EDGE Level C Curriculum Guide LANGUAGE DEVELOPMENT VOCABULARY COMMON WRITING PROJECT. ToolKit

Maximizing Learning Through Course Alignment and Experience with Different Types of Knowledge

AN INTRODUCTION (2 ND ED.) (LONDON, BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC PP. VI, 282)

Transcription:

On the force of V2 declaratives* Hans-Martin Gartner (ZAS Berlin) gaertner@zas.gwz-berlin.de Abstract: This paper discusses a variant of German V2 declaratives sharing properties with both subordinate relative clauses and main clauses. I argue that modal subordination failure helps decide between two rivaling accounts for this construction. Thus, a hypotactic analysis involving syntactic variable sharing must be preferred over parataxis plus anaphora resolution. The scopal behavior of the construction will be derived from its 'proto-assertional force,' which it shares with similar 'embedded root' constructions. It is well-known that the syntactic position of finite verbs in German is sensitive to the main vs. subordinate clause distinction. VI and V2 structures tend to be main clauses while V-final order usually indicates subordination. However, exceptions in both directions have repeatedly been reported and even studied in more or less detail (cf. Reis 1997 and references cited there.) Here I would like to further our understanding of 'embedded V2' declarative clauses by investigating the following question. (1) QI: Are there V2 relative clauses in German? I suggest that a proper answer to Q1 requires close analysis of minimal triples like the following. (Finite verbs are underlined in the relevant clauses.) (2) a. Das Blatt hat eine Seite (I), die ganz schwarz &. the sheet has one side that entirely black is 'That sheet of paper has one side that is entirely black' b. Das Blatt hat eine Seite (I), die & ganz schwarz. c. #Das Blatt hat eine Seite (\). Die & ganz schwarz. While (2a) involves a standard V-final relative clause and (2c) displays the sequence of two independent main clauses, the status of (2b) is unclear. This will be reflected in the following terminological convention. (3) Terminological Convention a. Call the second clause in (2b) 'V2 Relative' (V2R) if you want to emphasize properties it shares with its counterpart in (24. For comments and suggestions, I would like to thank the participants of the workshop on 'Informationsstruktur und der referentielle Status von sprachlichen Ausdriicken' at the DGfS meeting in Leipzig (2001) and the one on 'The Roots of Pragmasemantics 11' in Szklarska Poreba (2001). The paper is submitted to a special issue of 'Theoretical Linguistics', edited by Klaus von Heusinger and Kerstin Schwabe ZAS Papers in Linguistics 23, 2001, 103-109

Hans-Martin Gartner b. Call the second clause in (2b) 'Integrated Verb Second' (IV2) if you want to emphasize properties it shares with its counterpart in (2c). Remaining neutral at this stage, I will conflate the two terms in (3) and refer to the sentence type at issue as 'V2WIV2.' To begin with, the following three properties of V2WIV2 should be noted. (4) (Curious) Properties of VZWIV2 a. V2WIV2 has to be immediately preceded by non-final phonological boundary marking (I). b. V2WIV2 can only modify indefinites in the putative matrix clause. c. V2RJIV2 is able to restrictively modify its antecedent. (4a) is important for distinguishing V2WIV2 from parenthetical counterparts, for which most of the generalizations discussed here do not hold. The issue of quantifiers compatible with V2WIV2 indicated in (4b) will not be taken up in this paper, although one way to account for it may be inferable from the analysis presented below.' (4c) can be substantiated by the observation that the initial clause in (2c) triggers the Horn-scale implicature (5). (5) The sheet of paper has no more than one side (5) arises in order to restore informativity to an otherwise vacuous sentence, given world knowledge such as is expressed in (6). (6) Vx [ Sheet of Paper (x) + 3Y [ Y = {z I Side of (z, x) ) A IYI = 2 ] ] The inconsistency of (5) and (6) then result in pragmatic anomaly (#). Crucially, implicature (5) does not arise with (2a) or (2b). This is evidence that there the initial clause is not evaluated in isolation. Instead the indefinite description is semantically intersected with the content of the adjacent clausal modifier, i.e. it is restrictively modified. Another curious property of V2WIV2 concerns scope. (4) d. V2WIV2 forces its indefinite antecedent to take wide scope, Thus, consider (7). (7) a. Maria mochte einen Fisch fangen (I), der kariert &. Maria wants a fish catch that checkered is 'Mary wants to catch a fish that is checkered' b. Maria mochte einen Fisch fangen (I), der & kariert. c. Maria mochte einen Fisch fangen (\). Der & kariert. Here only (7a) is neutral as for the scope of the indefinite. (7b) and (7c), on the other hand, invariably induce a de re reading. In order to account for that effect, we may assimilate (7b) to (7c) on the basis of (8). 1 For detailed discussion and an account based on different premises, see Gartner (1998, forthcoming) 104

On the force of V2 declaratives (8) Paratactic Hypothesis (PH)~ V2WIV2 is a case of parataxis. This could be fleshed out syntactically by postulating the existence of a functional category z~, which takes V2RIIV2 as its complement and another clause containing an indefinite as its specifier. (9) illustrates that idea. PH predicts that V2WIV2 involves anaphora resolution like (7c), that process being subject to standard conditions on accessibility. Therefore, (7b) would require a de re reading of the indefinite. A closer look at pronouns linking the two clauses provides a fairly subtle additional argument in favor of PH and the concomitant amphora-resolution view of V2WIV2. (2) has already shown that all three constructions tolerate weak demonstratives. (10) adds w-pronouns and personal pronouns, none of which can figure in V2RlIV2. (10) a. Das Blatt hat eine Seite (/), welche ganz schwarz &. b. *Das Blatt hat eine Seite (I), sie ganz schwarz &. c. *Das Blatt hat eine Seite (I), welche & ganz schwarz. d. *Das Blatt hat eine Seite (/), sie ganz schwarz. e. *Das Blatt hat eine Seite (\). Welche & ganz schwarz. f. #Das Blatt hat eine Seite (\). Sie & ganz schwarz. This is summarized in (I I) (wd = weak demonstrative; w = w-pronoun; pers = personal pronoun). (11) Pronoun Compatibility a. Standard Relative Clauses: [+ wd I/ [ + w I/ [ - pers ] b. V2RlIV2: [+wd]/ [-w]/[-pers ] c. Cross-sentential anaphora: [+wd]l[-w]/[+pers] The following paradigm, again in the domain of weak demonstratives, provides the crucial contrast. (12) a. *Es gibt Lander (I), da das Bier ein Vermogen m. It gives countries there the beer a fortune costs b. Es gibt Lander (/), da- das Bier ein Vermogen. c. #Es gibt Lander (\). Da koster das Bier ein Vermogen. While most weak demonstratives are (homonyms of) relative pronouns, the pronoun da ('there') is not. It can be used in contexts of cross-sentential anaphora but is banned from V-final relative clauses. Its compatibility with V2WIV2 (12b) indicates that this construction patterns with cross-sentential anaphora. However, the picture just outlined must be further complicated in the light of the following question. See Girtner (1998, forthcoming) for a comprehensive version of PH, including independent empirical evidence and a DRS-update mechanism able to cope with (most of) the scope facts. 105

Hans-Martin Gartne~ (1 3) 42: Does PH predict the possibility of modal subordination for V2lUIV2? Curiously, this prediction underlying PH/Q2 is not borne out, as (14) demonstrates. (14) a. Maria mochte einen Fisch fangen (I), den sie essen m. Maria want a fish catch that she eat could 'Mary wants to catch a fish that she could eat' b. *Maria mochte einen Fisch fangen (I), den kiinnte sie essen. c. Maria mochte einen Fisch fangen (\). Den sie essen. Note, however, that property (4a) makes one suspect that V2WIV2 does not give rise to text formation the way a sequence of sentences does. In fact, integration into the preceding clause is obligatory, given property (4e). (4) e. V2FUIV2 forms an 'information unit,' definable as a single partition into focus and background, with its putative matrix clause. (4e) is one of the essential building blocks in developing a formal account for the facts in (14). Thus, according to Groenendijk&Stokhof (1989) (cf. Honcoop 1998, Saeb0 1999). modal subordination involves a propositional discourse referent provided by an antecedent clause and picked up by a covert anaphor in the restrictor of a modal operator in the follow-up clause.' Given (4e), however, V2WIV2 is itself part of the minimal proposition able to provide the required discourse referent. That is, V2WIV2 is evaluated before the required discourse referent may become available. Therefore, modal subordination must fail and unacceptability of (14b) is predicted.4 Unfortunately, this way of dealing with (14b) runs into additional problems with PA. Q3 formulates the relevant issue. (15) Q3: Doesn't PH rely on the mechanism of anaphora resolution and thus evaluation of V2RlIV2 after evaluation of the putative matrix clause? Clearly, in order to avoid contradiction I must revise PH. I suggest that PH be replaced by (16).~ Concretely, Groenendijk&Stokhof (1989:38ff) argue that (i) should be given the meaning in (ii), (i) Ein Tiger konnte hereinkommen (\I. Der wiirde dich zuerst fressen. (ii) Possibly (a tiger comas in) and necessarily (if a tiger comes in, it eats you first) Technically this is implemented as in (iii). (iii) a. would v= hp 1 I "D,,,,,,,,, VJ I A "p I b. possibly $ = EDhp [ 0.1 'D A "p I(@) 'by dynamic conjunction' + 'some plausible assumptions about the semantics of this extension of DIL' + 'some obvious reductions': c. hp10.1$~ L[O*VIA"PI Crucially, the indefinite in + becomes accessible for dynamic binding of a pronoun in y, within the scope of. As far as I can see, this account carries over to the presuppositional theory of modal subordination developed in Geurts (1999). This move will leave the above mentioned pronoun facts without a satisfactory account.

On the force of V2 declaratives (16) Hypotactic Hypothesis (HH) V2WIV2 is a case of standard (relative clause) hypotaxis. Under HH, V2WIV2 would share a variable with its indefinite antecedent, due to syntactic copying. Thus, the issue of anaphora resolution does not arise. Of course, HH generates the follow-up question in (17). (17) 44: How can V2WIV2 and standard relative clauses be distinguished on the basis of HH? The answer to 44 lies in property (40, the final one discussed in this paper. (4) f. V2WIV2 is an instance of 'embedded root phenomena' (a.k.a. 'dependent main clause phenomena'). Building on earlier work in this area (cf. Hooper&Thompson 1973, Wechsler 1991, Reis 1997), I would like to defend the following hypothesis. (18) Proto-Force Hypothesis (PFH) V2 declaratives have proto-assertional force Proto-assertional force forces V2RIIV2 together with its indefinite antecedent out of the scope of modal operators and negation (among many others). Interaction with negation is documented in (19). (19) a. Kein Professori mag eine Studentin (I), [ die ihni nicht ] No professor likes a female student who him not cites 'No professor likes a female student that doesn't cite him' b. *Kein Professori mag eine Studentin (I), [ die zitiert ihni nicht ] Since the negative quantifier in (19) binds the personal pronoun, the modifying clause is forced into the scope of negation. This fails in the case of V2RIIV2. My claim then is that combining HH and PFH properly treats the properties of V2RIIV2. HH prevents modal subordination, which accounts for the unacceptability of (14b). PFH prevents syntactic 'scopal subordination.' This predicts the unacceptability of (l4b) and (19b), as well as the unavailability of a de dicto reading in (7b). At this stage, I cannot present a formal theory underlying PFH. Yet, a number of adequacy criteria indicative of the structure of such a theory are fairly clear. Thus, consider (20). (20) Adequacy Criterion for PFH 'Embedded Force Exclusion' should be met. This well-known issue has recently been raised again by Green (2000, p.440). (2 1) Embedded Force Exclusion (EFE) If cp is either a part of speech or a sentence, and cp contains some indicator f of illocutionary force, then cp does not embed.

Hans-Martin Gartner Thus, it is preferable to avoid simplistic direct endowment of V2 declaratives with assertional force (potential). This requirement is met by PFH. Proto-forces will then have to be supplemented by (projection) rules of the following kind. (22) Proto-Assertional Force Construal a. Unembedded proto-assertional force translates into assertional force (potential). b. Embedded proto-assertional force can be 'absorbed' by assertional force (potential) if there is no intervener. c. Embedded proto-assertional force can be 'absorbed' on arguments of predicates that denote acts of assertion etc. d. Non-absorbed proto-assertional force leads to semanticlpragmatic deviance. (22c) takes care of complementation by V2 clauses, the content of which is not a speaker assertion. An example is given in (23). (23) Ich hoffe du glaubst mir I hope you believe me The main theoretical burden of (22) rests on a notion of 'intervener,' which will have to be the subject of further re~earch.~ In sum, I have argued that V2RlIV2 should be given a hypotactic analysis. Its scopal behavior, resulting in modal subordination failure, must be derived from its protoassertional force. Proto-force in turn should be linked to the embedded root nature of V2RlIV2. If such an analysis is on the right track it would also justify giving a positive answer to question Q1. References: Gartner, Hans-Martin (1998): "Does German Have V2 Relative Clauses?" Sprache zrnd Praglnatik 48. Giirtner, Hans-Martin (forthcoming): "Are There V2 Relative Clauses in German?" Journal of Conlparative Gen?~anic Lir~gz~isfics 3.3. Geurts, Bart (1999): PI-emppositions and Pronouns. Oxford: Elsevier. 6 To the extent that material in the scope of a universal quantifier is not (directly) asserted, universal quantifiers may count as 'interveners.' It is therefore important to note that V2MV2 can - under certain conditions (see Gartner 1998, forthcoming) - modify an ~ndefinite in the scope of a universal quantifier. This is shown in (i). (i) a. Jedes Haus hat ein Zimmer, [ in dem & es gemiitlich ] Everj house has a room in thatdar is it COS)' h. Jeder Berg; hat eine Flanke, [ uber die & eri sich leicht besteigen I Evev nlountain has a face over thatacc lets it itselfeasil)' climb 'Every mountain has a face across which one can climb it easily.' However, a functional interpretation of the indefinite as proposed by Groenendijk&Stokhof (1984) would remove the content of V2RIIV2 from the scope of the universal quantifier ever)' house, as indicated in (ii). (ii) 3f[ R(f) A Vx.COSY-ROOM(f(x)) A Vy[ HOUSE(y) + HAVE( y, f(y)) I I

On the force of V2 declaratives Green, Mitchell S. (2000): "Illocutionary Force and Semantic Content," Lingnistics and Philosophy 23: 435-473. Groenendijk, Jeroen & Martin Stokhof (1984): "Interrogative Quantifiers and Skolem functions," In Groenendijk,J.&M.Stokhof, Studies on the Semat~tics of Questions and the Pragmatics of Answers, Ph.D. dissertation, University of Amsterdam. 165-208. Groenendijk, Jeroen & Martin Stokhof (1989): "Dynamic Montague Grammar," ITLI Prepublication Series X-89-04. University of Amsterdam. Honcoop, Martin (1998): Dynamic Excursions on Weak 1slrmrl.s. The Hague: Holland Academic Graphics. Hooper, Joan & Sandra Thompson (1973) "On the Applicability of Root Transformations," Linguistic Inquir)' 4: 465-497. Reis, Marga (1997): "Zum syntaktischen Status unselbstiindiger Verbzweit Satze," In D'Avis, F. & U. Lutz (eds.), "Zur Satzstruktur des Deutschen," Arbeitspapiere des SFB 340 Nr. 90. Stuttgart and Tubingen. 121-142. Szba, Kjell Johan (1999): "Discourse Linking and Discourse Subordination." in Bosch, P. & R. van der Sandt (eds.), Focus. Cambridge: CUP. 322-335. Wechsler, Stephen (1991): "Verb Second and Illocutionary Force." in Leffel, K. & D. Bouchard (eds.), Views on Phrase Strnctrrre. Dordrecht: Kluwer. 177-1 91.