Fenstad, Jens Erik: Grammar, Geometry, & Brain. CSLI Lecture Notes. CSLI Pages.

Similar documents
Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

Some Principles of Automated Natural Language Information Extraction

An Introduction to the Minimalist Program

LFG Semantics via Constraints

South Carolina English Language Arts

The Strong Minimalist Thesis and Bounded Optimality

An Interactive Intelligent Language Tutor Over The Internet

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

THEORETICAL CONSIDERATIONS

Module 12. Machine Learning. Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

Abstractions and the Brain

Radius STEM Readiness TM

Mathematics Program Assessment Plan

Lecture 9. The Semantic Typology of Indefinites

Maximizing Learning Through Course Alignment and Experience with Different Types of Knowledge

Physics 270: Experimental Physics

Evolution of Symbolisation in Chimpanzees and Neural Nets

UCLA Issues in Applied Linguistics

Specification and Evaluation of Machine Translation Toy Systems - Criteria for laboratory assignments

Guidelines for Writing an Internship Report

Learning Methods for Fuzzy Systems

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

DIDACTIC MODEL BRIDGING A CONCEPT WITH PHENOMENA

LING 329 : MORPHOLOGY

Learning Disability Functional Capacity Evaluation. Dear Doctor,

The Effect of Discourse Markers on the Speaking Production of EFL Students. Iman Moradimanesh

AQUA: An Ontology-Driven Question Answering System

- «Crede Experto:,,,». 2 (09) ( '36

Self Study Report Computer Science

First Grade Curriculum Highlights: In alignment with the Common Core Standards

THE ANTINOMY OF THE VARIABLE: A TARSKIAN RESOLUTION Bryan Pickel and Brian Rabern University of Edinburgh

Room: Office Hours: T 9:00-12:00. Seminar: Comparative Qualitative and Mixed Methods

Objectives. Chapter 2: The Representation of Knowledge. Expert Systems: Principles and Programming, Fourth Edition

Parallel Evaluation in Stratal OT * Adam Baker University of Arizona

Math-U-See Correlation with the Common Core State Standards for Mathematical Content for Third Grade

BENG Simulation Modeling of Biological Systems. BENG 5613 Syllabus: Page 1 of 9. SPECIAL NOTE No. 1:

What is PDE? Research Report. Paul Nichols

Syllabus: Introduction to Philosophy

arxiv: v1 [math.at] 10 Jan 2016

Som and Optimality Theory

Writing a composition

Inquiry Learning Methodologies and the Disposition to Energy Systems Problem Solving

WHY SOLVE PROBLEMS? INTERVIEWING COLLEGE FACULTY ABOUT THE LEARNING AND TEACHING OF PROBLEM SOLVING

EQuIP Review Feedback

Page 1 of 11. Curriculum Map: Grade 4 Math Course: Math 4 Sub-topic: General. Grade(s): None specified

Topic Study Group No. 25: The Role of History of Mathematics in Mathematics Education

A cautionary note is research still caught up in an implementer approach to the teacher?

TEACHING AND EXAMINATION REGULATIONS PART B: programme-specific section MASTER S PROGRAMME IN LOGIC

Ontologies vs. classification systems

COMPUTATIONAL COMPLEXITY OF LEFT-ASSOCIATIVE GRAMMAR

Probabilistic Latent Semantic Analysis

Notes on The Sciences of the Artificial Adapted from a shorter document written for course (Deciding What to Design) 1

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

Proposal of Pattern Recognition as a necessary and sufficient principle to Cognitive Science

1 st Quarter (September, October, November) August/September Strand Topic Standard Notes Reading for Literature

LEXICAL COHESION ANALYSIS OF THE ARTICLE WHAT IS A GOOD RESEARCH PROJECT? BY BRIAN PALTRIDGE A JOURNAL ARTICLE

Mathematics subject curriculum

SARDNET: A Self-Organizing Feature Map for Sequences

Full text of O L O W Science As Inquiry conference. Science as Inquiry

Assessment System for M.S. in Health Professions Education (rev. 4/2011)

Designing a Rubric to Assess the Modelling Phase of Student Design Projects in Upper Year Engineering Courses

On-Line Data Analytics

Major Milestones, Team Activities, and Individual Deliverables

UNIVERSITY OF THESSALY DEPARTMENT OF EARLY CHILDHOOD EDUCATION POSTGRADUATE STUDIES INFORMATION GUIDE

THE ROLE OF TOOL AND TEACHER MEDIATIONS IN THE CONSTRUCTION OF MEANINGS FOR REFLECTION

Reviewed by Florina Erbeli

Highlighting and Annotation Tips Foundation Lesson

English Language and Applied Linguistics. Module Descriptions 2017/18

Lecturing Module

21 st Century Skills and New Models of Assessment for a Global Workplace

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Using Calculators for Students in Grades 9-12: Geometry. Re-published with permission from American Institutes for Research

Agent-Based Software Engineering

Developing True/False Test Sheet Generating System with Diagnosing Basic Cognitive Ability

EDITORIAL: ICT SUPPORT FOR KNOWLEDGE MANAGEMENT IN CONSTRUCTION

Graduate Program in Education

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

Applications of memory-based natural language processing

Digital Fabrication and Aunt Sarah: Enabling Quadratic Explorations via Technology. Michael L. Connell University of Houston - Downtown

Evolution of Collective Commitment during Teamwork

New Ways of Connecting Reading and Writing

The Intertwining Influences of Logic, Philosophy, and Linguistics in the Development of Formal Semantics and Pragmatics.

Segmented Discourse Representation Theory. Dynamic Semantics with Discourse Structure

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

Language Acquisition Fall 2010/Winter Lexical Categories. Afra Alishahi, Heiner Drenhaus

Authors note Chapter One Why Simpler Syntax? 1.1. Different notions of simplicity

Montana Content Standards for Mathematics Grade 3. Montana Content Standards for Mathematical Practices and Mathematics Content Adopted November 2011

Timeline. Recommendations

1 3-5 = Subtraction - a binary operation

Introducing the New Iowa Assessments Language Arts Levels 15 17/18

TABE 9&10. Revised 8/2013- with reference to College and Career Readiness Standards

PROGRAMME SPECIFICATION

MASTER S THESIS GUIDE MASTER S PROGRAMME IN COMMUNICATION SCIENCE

HISTORY COURSE WORK GUIDE 1. LECTURES, TUTORIALS AND ASSESSMENT 2. GRADES/MARKS SCHEDULE

PH.D. IN COMPUTER SCIENCE PROGRAM (POST M.S.)

AGS THE GREAT REVIEW GAME FOR PRE-ALGEBRA (CD) CORRELATED TO CALIFORNIA CONTENT STANDARDS

Transcription:

Fenstad, Jens Erik: Grammar, Geometry, & Brain. CSLI Lecture Notes. CSLI 2010. 111 Pages. In this small book logician and mathematician Jens Erik Fenstad addresses some of the most important foundational questions of linguistics: What should a theory of meaning look like and how might we provide the missing link between meaning theory and our knowledge of how the brain works? The author s answer is twofold. On the one hand, he suggests that logical semantics in the Montague tradition and other broadly conceived symbolic approaches do not suffice. On the other hand, he does not argue that the logical approach should be discarded; instead, he opts for a methodological pluralism in which symbolic approaches to meaning are combined with geometric ones such as Conceptual Spaces [9] and discusses ways in which these geometric accounts could be hooked up with connectionist frameworks and dynamic systems approaches in neurophysiology. The book is divided into three chapters to be summarized in the following paragraphs. In the first chapter Fenstad addresses the history of linguistic theory and what one might call the traditional convictions of linguistics. The historical part comprises an overview of the early development of grammar and logic, briefly mentioning works of thinkers like Plato, Aristotle, Boethius, Dionysius Thrax, Apollonius Dyscolus, the modistae, Thomas of Erfurt s Grammatica Speculativa, and the Port Royal logicians. The author then jumps to the rise of modern linguistics and semantics. Concerning syntax, linguists like Saussure, Bloomfield, and Jespersen are acknowledged, yet not discussed in great detail. Turning to semantics, Fenstad draws a line from the work of Tarski, Ajdukiewicz and Lesniewski of the Lvov-Warsaw school over Reichenbach, Bar-Hillel, and Curry to Montague. Apart from roughly laying out the historical development, one of his main points of this part is that often contingencies played a role in the success or failure of semantic and linguistic programs. For example, Fenstad argues that although Curry s work already contained all the potential for this kind of semantics, Montague succeeded in spreading Curry s and his own ideas partly because Barbara Hall Partee helped popularize his work. In the second part of the chapter, Fenstad discusses, amongst other things, the connection between syntax and semantics, which following [12] he characterizes as a mapping from a computational module representing the syntactic domain to a conceptual module representing meaning. This mapping is achieved by a connecting sign : a projection rule in the Chomskian tradition, and in the tradition of categorial grammar the application of shifted types that reduce to base types which reflect the underlying combinatory model structure. For instance, a shifted verb entry such as love (P )(x) defined as 1

P (λy.love (x, y)), where love denotes a relation between two individuals, in a simple example allows one to retain the main distribution patterns of generalized quantifiers and proper names while in the meantime keeping the underlying higher-order logic term love conventional of type eet (or, σιι in the notation of Church and Henkin). The reader who would expect to hear more about extensions of Applicative Categorial Grammar such as [15, 2, 13], in which most type-shifting principles are provable, or more about standard analyses like [20] will be disappointed, for the discussion instead turns to some work with which the author himself was involved: using attribute value structures as situation schemata and embedding these into lexical functional grammar. Taking a look at a relatively detailed example based on [8] it is argued that attribute value structures constitute a qualitative shift from defining the syntax-semantics interface as a homomorphism between two algebras to a constraint-based view of the relationship between form and meaning and that this latter view is more fruitful. The chapter ends with a very brief and somewhat detached discussion of language technology in order to illustrate that grammar and meaning is an interdisciplinary matter. The second chapter primarily deals with geometric approaches to meaning such as Gärdenfors s Conceptual Spaces [9]. One aim of this chapter is to show that symbolic/logical approaches ought to be supplemented by geometric ones. Why? To make the point, the author resorts to the theory of the evolution of culture and cognition of [4]. (The interested reader might take a look at [5] for an overview.) According to Donald, the evolution of cognition is divided into four phases: episodic, mimetic, mythic, and theoretical culture. These correspond to different stages of the biological and cultural evolution from the homo erectus to the homo sapiens. Now Fenstad s point is that logical approaches based on first-order logic basically structure their domain as a large flat database, as relations are interpreted over Cartesian products of the total domain. Such a database structure suffices for simple models at the level of theoretical culture, but for an integrated understanding of discourse in context Donald s other levels need to be modeled as well. As Fenstad lays out, such models require more structure geometrical and topological approaches as for example Gärdenfors s Conceptual Spaces illustrate. While it would be possible to axiomatize these structures in higher-order logics it is well-known that these lack completeness and compactness with standard models and in fact higher-order logic is barely used for axiomatizing geometric or topological concepts. Fenstad does not mention such axiomatizations by the automated theorem prover community, but nevertheless he has a point. Linguists and logicians doing truth-conditional semantics do not use much structure and, as one might add, many linguists presume Henkin models anyway. As Fenstad further lays out, refinements and extensions such 2

as situation theory, possible worlds semantics, event and temporal logics, and partial models serve their purpose but do in practice not overcome the lack of structure in the models. As he puts it, [f]ormal semantics must proceed beyond the equation model = data base in order to serve as a link between language and mind [p. 33], and... meaning is a conceptualization in a cognitive model, not truth conditions in possible worlds. [p. 47] Perhaps surprisingly, he mentions reciprocals and locatives as examples of linguistic phenomena that require geometrical models; vagueness and similarity measures are not mentioned at this place and only addressed very briefly later. After this critical discussion, a short introduction to Conceptual Spaces is given. A Conceptual Space is an n-dimensional metric space where each dimension represents a quality like loudness, hue, or color saturation and dimensions may also have weights. Individual objects are vectors and concepts regions in that space. Not only can distance measures account for the similarity of objects and concepts in this kind of model, Gärdenfors also suggests to require a natural concept to be represented by a convex region, i.e. a region such that the points on the line segment between any two points in it are also in it, and points out that if conceptual spaces are arranged in a Voronoi tessellation, their centers can be taken to represent prototypes. Fenstad concurs and, going one step further than Gärdenfors, considers possible links between Conceptual Spaces and dynamic systems used in modeling brain dynamics such as attractor neural networks in [1]. The idea here is that... prototypes are the attractors of the system and the concept [... ] corresponds to a domain of attraction in the energy surface of the system. [p. 50] Thom s semiotics based on Catastrophe Theory [22, 23] is discussed as another possible way to provide a missing link between dynamic models of the mind/brain and symbolic computation. The gist of this chapter is that Conceptual Spaces and other broadly-conceived geometric models of meaning could serve as a mediator between symbolic computation and brain dynamics, potentially encompassing several or even all of Donald s levels of cognitive evolution. In the third and last chapter, Fenstad explores in more detail possible ways to provide the missing link between the geometric representations of the conceptual system and the dynamics of the brain. The chapter starts with Chomsky s question whether there is a Universal Grammar and how language might have evolved. The author does not give any definite answer to the question of the innateness of UG, but instead lays out work by mathematical biologist Nowak and his co-workers [18, 19] who show by means of dynamic evolutionary models how syntactic structures might have evolved and even provide an explicit threshold that indicates within the model when it becomes evolutionary advantageous to use signals with syntactic structure 3

rather than single signal communication. Fenstad then addresses reductionism and the question of hard AI, writing that [it] is generally accepted that an understanding of consciousness and self-awareness is basic for any final theory of language and meaning. [p. 72] Will we be able to write equations for consciousness some day, as [3] has suggested? Based on [7] Fenstad answers that in non-linear complex dynamic systems we see new phenomena emerge and... we may be have both upwards and downwards causality. [ibid.] Leaving this matter aside, the author then returns to the question of modeling at the mid-level by mapping from brain dynamics to geometric representations. Two suggestions are laid out in some more detail than others mentioned: Optimality and Harmony Theory [21] and an account based on Control Theory by [6]. It would take too much space to go into the details of these theories and Fenstad also summarizes them only cursorily. His general suggestion is as follows: Encode the representational form of meaning in attribute-value matrices, for example instances of situation schemata, and interpret these in suitable geometric models. Then link them to brain dynamics using whatever methodology seems suitable. Possible candidates for providing the missing link are for instance mean field theory, dynamic systems theory, control theory, and optimality theory. What to make of this book? It is best described as a subjective literature overview. As such, a reader cannot expect rigid argumentation or the level of detail of a textbook. None of the theories mentioned are discussed at great length and some parts of the book presume prior familiarity with the theories and their mathematical underpinnings. Moreover, the literature is not laid out in a systematic way but rather whenever the author deems it appropriate. There are also a few omissions that some logicians, semanticists, and philosophers might bemoan. Axiomatic and proof-theoretic semantics are not considered, seminal work in dynamic semantics such as [11, 10] and recent work by van Benthem and other researchers of the Amsterdam school of dynamic logics are barely mentioned. Hyperintensional logics such as [16, 17] where meanings (senses) are algorithms and alternative semantic foundations such as trope theories with topological semantics [14] are not discussed either. Of course, it would not be reasonable to expect a complete literature survey in such a small book, but in light of these omissions Fenstad s critique on the flat database approach of logic must be taken with a grain of salt. Another point worth mentioning is that not much ink is wasted on philosophical issues. Not everybody will consider this a shortcoming, but it can be misleading at times. For example, semantic internalism seems to be presumed throughout the book without mention, although many contemporary semanticists in the Montague tradition are social externalists about meaning. To give another example, the author considers it obvious that talking about 4

the brain as a computer is merely meant as a metaphor [p. 89], whereas to many computationalists (including some connectionists) this talk is not metaphorical at all in their view the mind/brain is a computer. These are minor shortcomings in an overall concise, inspiring and interesting book that feels a bit like a popular science book for experts. Fenstad has managed to jam together a wealth of information and common and uncommon references on less than a hundred pages that will make the book interesting to philosophers, linguists, cognitive scientists and anyone else working on meaning, concept systems, and the connection these have with the brain. The mathematical modeling perspective advocated in this book is in a stark and welcome contrast to certain foundational views about truth-conditional meaning that are in the reviewer s opinion less fruitful and still encountered frequently in philosophical semantics and the philosophy of language. Logic is a tool, but not the tool for doing semantics. To end with Fenstad s own words, the hope is that... someone from the next generation, well-trained in the mathematical sciences, will read the text and be encouraged to apply their particular skills to the complex problems of language, meaning, and the brain. [p. VII] References [1] Daniel J. Amit. Modeling Brain Function. Cambridge University Press, 1989. [2] Bob Carpenter. Type-Logical Semantics. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1997. [3] J. P. Changeux. Clarifying consciousness. Nature, 428:603 604, 2004. [4] Merlin Donald. Origin of the Modern Mind. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1990. [5] Merlin Donald. Precis and discussion of origin of the modern mind. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16:737 791, 1993. [6] C. Eliasmith and C. H. Anderson. Neural Engineering. MIT Press, 2003. [7] G. Ellis. Physics, complexity and causality. Nature, 435:743, 2005. [8] Jens Erik Fenstad, Per-Kristian Halvorsen, Tore Langholm, and Johan van Benthem. Situations, Language and Logic. D. Reidel, Amsterdam, 1987. 5

[9] Peter Gärdenfors. Conceptual Spaces. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 2000. [10] Irene Heim. File change semantics and the familiarity theory of definiteness. In Bäuerle, Schwarze, and von Stechow, editors, Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of Language. De Gruyter, 1983. [11] Hans Kamp and Uwe Reyle. From Discourse to Logic. Kluwer, 1993. [12] Jan Koster. How natural is natural language? In Jens Erik Fenstad, Ivan Timofeevich Frolov, and Risto Hilpinen, editors, Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science VIII, volume 126 of Studies in Logic, pages 591 606. Elsevier, Amsterdam, 1989. [13] Michael Moortgat. Categorial type logics. In Johan van Benthem and Alice ter Meulen, editors, Handbook of Logic and Language, pages 93 178. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1997. [14] Thomas Mormann. Trope sheaves: A topological ontology of tropes. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 3:129 150, 1995. [15] Glynn Morrill. Type Logical Grammar: Categorial Logic of signs. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, 1994. [16] Yiannis N. Moschovakis. Sense and denotation as algorithm and value. In J. Väänänen and J. Oikkonen, editors, Logic Colloquium 90, volume 2, pages 210 249. Association for Symbolic Logic, 1994. [17] Yiannis N. Moschovakis. A logical calculus of meaning and synonymy. Linguistics and Philosophy, 29(1):27 89, 2006. [18] M. A. Nowak, J. B. Plotkin, and V. A. A. Jansen. The evolution of syntactic communication. Nature, 404:495 498. [19] Martin A. Nowak. Evolutionary Dynamics. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 2006. [20] Barbara Hall Partee. Noun phrase interpretation and type-shifting principles. In Jeroen Groenendijk, Dick de Jongh, and Martin Stokhof, editors, Studies in Discourse Representation Theory and the Theory of Generalized Quantifiers, pages 115 143. Foris, Dordrecht, 1986. [21] Paul Smolensky and Géraldine Legendre. The Harmonic Mind, Vol. 1 and 2. MIT Press, 2006. 6

[22] René Thom. Topologie et linguistique. In A. Haefliger and R. Narasimhan, editors, Essays on Topology, pages 226 248. Springer, New York, 1970. [23] René Thom. Langage et catastrophes. In M. Peixoto, editor, Dynamical Systems, pages 619 654. Academic Press, New York, 1973. Erich Rast Institute for the Philosophy of Language (IFL) New University of Lisbon, Portugal erich@snafu.de akira.ruc.dk/~erast/ 7