The Bulgarian Reportative as a Conventional Implicature Chronos 10. Dimka Atanassov University of Pennsylvania

Similar documents
Focusing bound pronouns

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

5. UPPER INTERMEDIATE

Rule-based Expert Systems

A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF MINNESOTA BY. Kaitlin Rose Johnson

Writing a composition

Today we examine the distribution of infinitival clauses, which can be

Rubric for Scoring English 1 Unit 1, Rhetorical Analysis

(Re)Formalizing the Imperative Sentence Type. David Medeiros,

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

1/20 idea. We ll spend an extra hour on 1/21. based on assigned readings. so you ll be ready to discuss them in class

Part I. Figuring out how English works

cambridge occasional papers in linguistics Volume 8, Article 3: 41 55, 2015 ISSN

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

Intension, Attitude, and Tense Annotation in a High-Fidelity Semantic Representation

Theoretical Syntax Winter Answers to practice problems

Control and Boundedness

What is a Mental Model?

Specification and Evaluation of Machine Translation Toy Systems - Criteria for laboratory assignments

The Effect of Discourse Markers on the Speaking Production of EFL Students. Iman Moradimanesh

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Written by: YULI AMRIA (RRA1B210085) ABSTRACT. Key words: ability, possessive pronouns, and possessive adjectives INTRODUCTION

Context-Sensitive Bidirectional OT: a New Approach to Russian Aspect

Discourse markers and grammaticalization

Calculators in a Middle School Mathematics Classroom: Helpful or Harmful?

MOODY SUBJUNCTIVE IN ROMANIAN *

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

Intensive Writing Class

Monitoring Metacognitive abilities in children: A comparison of children between the ages of 5 to 7 years and 8 to 11 years

Realization of Textual Cohesion and Coherence in Business Letters through Presupposition 1

A New Semantics for Number

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

Compositional Semantics

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

California Department of Education English Language Development Standards for Grade 8

Developing Grammar in Context

Monsters and the theoretical role of context

Agree or Move? On Partial Control Anna Snarska, Adam Mickiewicz University

Section 7, Unit 4: Sample Student Book Activities for Teaching Listening

Declarative Questions

Possessive have and (have) got in New Zealand English Heidi Quinn, University of Canterbury, New Zealand

Word Stress and Intonation: Introduction

WE GAVE A LAWYER BASIC MATH SKILLS, AND YOU WON T BELIEVE WHAT HAPPENED NEXT

Dale Carnegie Final Results Package. For. Dale Carnegie Course DC218 Graduated 6/19/13

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

a) analyse sentences, so you know what s going on and how to use that information to help you find the answer.

Argument structure and theta roles

Modal Verbs for the Advice Move in Advice Columns

Korean ECM Constructions and Cyclic Linearization

P-4: Differentiate your plans to fit your students

FUZZY EXPERT. Dr. Kasim M. Al-Aubidy. Philadelphia University. Computer Eng. Dept February 2002 University of Damascus-Syria

Degree Comparisons across Possible Worlds: Measure Phrase Modification with -(i)na *

Prewriting: Drafting: Revising: Editing: Publishing:

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

Beyond constructions:

Exploration. CS : Deep Reinforcement Learning Sergey Levine

AN INTRODUCTION (2 ND ED.) (LONDON, BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC PP. VI, 282)

TU-E2090 Research Assignment in Operations Management and Services

Getting Started with Deliberate Practice

Strategic discourse comprehension

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Introduction to the Common European Framework (CEF)

The Structure of Relative Clauses in Maay Maay By Elly Zimmer

AN ANALYSIS OF GRAMMTICAL ERRORS MADE BY THE SECOND YEAR STUDENTS OF SMAN 5 PADANG IN WRITING PAST EXPERIENCES

Parsing of part-of-speech tagged Assamese Texts

Predatory Reading, & Some Related Hints on Writing. I. Suggestions for Reading

Simple Random Sample (SRS) & Voluntary Response Sample: Examples: A Voluntary Response Sample: Examples: Systematic Sample Best Used When

Critical Thinking in Everyday Life: 9 Strategies

Knowledge based expert systems D H A N A N J A Y K A L B A N D E

Relevance Theory and the saying/implicating distinction *

Does Linguistic Communication Rest on Inference?

Conversation Starters: Using Spatial Context to Initiate Dialogue in First Person Perspective Games

MASN: 1 How would you define pragmatics today? How is it different from traditional Greek rhetorics? What are its basic tenets?

...WE CAN DO BETTER TIN-dag 2012, February 4, 2012

Type-driven semantic interpretation and feature dependencies in R-LFG

Teachers Guide Chair Study

Why Pay Attention to Race?

Transitive meanings for intransitive verbs

Cal s Dinner Card Deals

Critical Thinking in the Workplace. for City of Tallahassee Gabrielle K. Gabrielli, Ph.D.

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

Criterion Met? Primary Supporting Y N Reading Street Comprehensive. Publisher Citations

Inleiding Taalkunde. Docent: Paola Monachesi. Blok 4, 2001/ Syntax 2. 2 Phrases and constituent structure 2. 3 A minigrammar of Italian 3

STUDENTS' RATINGS ON TEACHER

Propositional Anaphora in English: The relationship between so and discourse

UCLA UCLA Electronic Theses and Dissertations

A Study of Metacognitive Awareness of Non-English Majors in L2 Listening

Modality in Typological Perspective

Red Flags of Conflict

Entrepreneurial Discovery and the Demmert/Klein Experiment: Additional Evidence from Germany

2014 Free Spirit Publishing. All rights reserved.

Mathematical Misconceptions -- Can We Eliminate Them? Phi lip Swedosh and John Clark The University of Melbourne. Introduction

Course Syllabus Advanced-Intermediate Grammar ESOL 0352

LEXICAL COHESION ANALYSIS OF THE ARTICLE WHAT IS A GOOD RESEARCH PROJECT? BY BRIAN PALTRIDGE A JOURNAL ARTICLE

Som and Optimality Theory

UKLO Round Advanced solutions and marking schemes. 6 The long and short of English verbs [15 marks]

Semantic Inference at the Lexical-Syntactic Level for Textual Entailment Recognition

Transcription:

The Bulgarian Reportative as a Conventional Implicature Chronos 10 Dimka Atanassov dimka@ling.upenn.edu University of Pennsylvania 1 / 35

Introduction The Bulgarian reportative is traditionally analyzed as marking the source of information as reported, or hearsay. An example from [Izvorski(1997)]. (1) Maria celunala Ivan Maria kiss-sg-pap Ivan Maria reportedly kissed Ivan In (1) the speaker wishes to convey that he knows from a third party that Maria kissed Ivan (i.e., has not witnessed or inferred the kissing event). The reportative in Bulgarian is optional (default may be used in lack of direct evidence). 2 / 35

Introduction (Contd.) Morphologically, the reportative looks like the perfect, but it is distinguished from it by the lack of auxiliary in the 3 rd person: (2) Pročel s@m tazi kniga read-sg-pap is-1sg-pres this book I have read this book /I have reportedly read this book (but I don t remember reading it; but I disagree with what is said about me) (3) Pročel si tazi kniga read-sg-pap is-2sg-pres this book You have read this book/ You have (reportedly) read this book (so you say; so someone says about you) (4) a. Ivan e pročel tazi kniga Ivan is-3sg-pres read-sg-pap this book Ivan has read this book. b. Ivan pročel tazi kniga Ivan read-sg-pap this book Ivan (reportedly) read this book. 3 / 35

Introduction (Contd.) Traditional view: reportative marks information source (hearsay). A broader perspective: the reportative serves as a non-committing device. (I keep referring to the morphological form as reportative ). Motivation: speakers will bother to use the reportative, rather than the default when they wish to emphasize that they are not committing to the trtuth of the proposition. Informal study, only 9 out of 30 participants found the reportative form acceptable in a matrix clause when the supporting evidence was reported but the source reliable. (another 3 were uncertain). 32 out of 34 found the default form acceptable in the same scenario. 4 / 35

In This Talk: (Non) embedability and the speaker oriented nature of the reportative. Implications of being speaker oriented (the reportative is a Conventional Implicature [Potts(2005)]). An analysis: The reportative and weak assertions: the idea of kernels in [von Fintel and Gillies(2010)] The reportative as a non commitment device: the discourse structure in [Farkas and Bruce(2010)]. 5 / 35

Structure: (Non) embedability and the speaker oriented nature of the reportative. Implications of being speaker oriented (the reportative is a Conventional Implicature [Potts(2005)]). An analysis: The reportative and weak assertions: the idea of kernels in [von Fintel and Gillies(2010)] The reportative as a non commitment device: the discourse structure in [Farkas and Bruce(2010)]. 6 / 35

Interpretation of Embedded Cases The Bulgarian reportative can be embedded, and when embedded it must always refer to the speaker (See [Sauerland and Schenner(2007)] for a similar point). (5) Maria kaza če Ivan celunal Ana Maria tell-3sg-aorist that Ivan kiss-sg-pap Ana Maria said that Ivan reportedly kissed Ana (5) has the following meaning: 1. Maria said that Ivan kissed Ana. 2. I (the speaker) do not want to commit to the proposition that Ivan kissed Ana And (5) lacks this meaning: 1. Maria said that Ivan kissed Ana. 2. Maria does not wish to commit to the proposition that Ivan kissed Ana 7 / 35

Interpretation of Embedded Cases (Contd.) Additional evidence for speaker oriented nature: Context: Onzi den vidjah Ivan da krade pari ot kazata. Kazah na Todor, no dvamata rešihme da si m@lčim zasega. Na sutrinta načalnika ni povika i ni popita otnosno lipsvaštite pari, i dali znaem koj gi e otkradnal. The other day I saw Ivan stealing from the cash register. I told Todor, but the two of us decided to keep quiet for the time being. The next morning our manager called us in and asked us about the money, and whether we know who had stolen it. (6) Todor kaza na načalnika che Ivan e kradeca. Todor say-3sg-aorist to manager-the that Ivan is-sg-pres thief-the. Todor told the manager that Ivan is the thief (7) # Todor kaza na načalnika che Ivan bil Todor say-3sg-aorist to manager-the that Ivan is-sg-pap kradeca. thief-the. Todor told the manager that Ivan reportedly is the thief 8 / 35

Interpretation of Embedded Cases (Contd.) If the reportative was able to refer to the subject of the matrix clause, (7) should have been felicitous under the following reading: 1. Todor told the manager that Ivan is the thief. 2. Todor did not commit himself to the proposition Ivan is the thief. The fact that (7) is infelicitous shows that such reading in fact does not exist. 9 / 35

Interpretation of Embedded Cases (Contd.) Consider furthermore: (8) # Maria ne mi kaza če Ivan celunal Maria neg me tell-3sg that Ivan kiss-sg-pap Ana, tja mi kaza če Ivan celuna Ana Ana, she me tell-3sg that Ivan kiss-3sg Ana Intended: Maria did not tell me that Ivan reportedly kissed Ana, she told me that Ivan kissed Ana If a subject oriented reading was possible, (8) would have been felicitous, under the following meaning: 1. Maria told me that Ivan kissed Ana 2. It is not the case that Maria is not committed to the kissing, in fact, she is. 10 / 35

Interpretation of Embedded Cases (Contd.) No subject oriented reading is available. The first part of (8) entails: 1. Maria did not tell me that Ivan kissed Ana 2. I (the speaker) do not wish to commit myself to the kissing (I wish to distance myself) The second part means: 1. Maria told me that Ivan kissed Ana Result: Maria did not tell me that Ivan kissed Ana, she told me that Ivan kissed Ana, and by the way, I do not want to commit myself to Ivan kissing Ana. 11 / 35

Interpretation of Embedded Cases (Contd.) Question: why use the reportative in embeddings in the first place? If the speaker is already embedding the clause under a verb of saying, then his speech act does not commit him to the proposition expressed by the embedded clause. So why the reportative? Embedding under a verb of saying does not eliminate the possibility that the speaker is committed to the proposition in the embedded clause. Consider the English example in (9): (9) Mommy said I can have a cookie. Here mommy, is used to give the proposition I can have a cookie more strength (by appealing to someone with greater authority). Thus it is not the case that embedding under a verb of saying eliminates any obligation that the speaker may have. 12 / 35

Structure: (Non) embedability and the speaker oriented nature of the reportative. Implications of being speaker oriented (the reportative is a Conventional Implicature [Potts(2005)]). An analysis: The reportative and weak assertions: the idea of kernels in [von Fintel and Gillies(2010)] The reportative as a non commitment device: the discourse structure in [Farkas and Bruce(2010)]. 13 / 35

Implications of being Speaker Oriented Incompatibility with a modal analysis: A modal analysis predicts that the reportative should be able to refer to the subject of the matrix clause, i.e. to be semantically embedded. But the Bulgarian reportative cannot refer to the subject of the matrix clause (See [Sauerland and Schenner(2007)] for a similar point). Incompatibility with an analysis as a presupposition. 14 / 35

Incompatibility with an analysis as a presupposition [Potts(2005)]: a presupposition may be eliminated by context, but not a conventional implicature: (10) Ed said that Sue realized it was raining. (Later, we found out that Ed s report was wrong. Sue can t have realized it was raining, because it wasn t) (11) Ed said that, as Sue predicted, it was raining.# But in fact Sue didn t predict rain. [Potts(2005)] Sue realized it was raining presupposes that it is raining. (10) lacks this presupposition, because Sue realized that it s raining is embedded under a verb of saying, a presupposition plug. Adding information that in fact Sue didn t realize it was raining is felicitous. The same cannot be done with conventional implicatures. In (11), the as-parenthetical is entailed even when inside a plug. 15 / 35

Incompatibility with an analysis as a presupposition Applying the same reasoning to the reportative: Let α be the inference that the speaker is not committing to the information conveyed by the embedded proposition. If α is a presupposition, then α could be eliminated by embedding, like in (10). If α cannot be eliminated in this way, this would be evidence that the Bulgarian reportative behaves as a Conventional Implicature. Just like CIs, the reportative is not canceled when embedded under a verb of saying. If it was cancelled, (7), repeated here, would have been felicitous in the above context, contrary to fact. (12) # Todor kaza Todor say-3sg-aorist bil kradeca. is-sg-pap thief-the. na to načalnika che Ivan manager-the that Ivan Todor told the manager that Ivan reportedly is the thief 16 / 35

A concord analysis ruled out Some embedded evidentials can receive a concord reading (for example in St at imcets in [Matthewson et al., (2006)]). Why not claim the same for the embedded reportatives in Bulgarian? Problem1: Embedding under a verb of saying is not the same as not vouching for: Strictly speaking embedding under a verb of saying lacks an implication that the speaker is vouching for the information expressed (i.e., from Mary said it is raining it does not follow that the speaker thinks it is raining) This is not incompatible with the speaker not vouching for the embedded proposition. For example: I know that it is raining, because Mary told me.. 17 / 35

A concord analysis ruled out Problem 2: reportatives may be embedded under other types of verbs (not just verbs of saying): Example: suppose that Elena is making a birthday cake for Ivan, and she asks me for advice on what kind of cake to make. I know (have direct evidence) that Ivan likes strawberries, I tell Elena this, but she forgets it, and does not put strawberries in Ivan s cake. Then (13) felicitous, but (14) is not. (13) Elena zabravi che Ivan običa jagodi. Elena forget-3sg-aorist that Ivan like-3sg-pres strawberries. Elena forgot that Ivan likes strawberries. (14) Elena zabravi che Ivan običal jagodi. Elena forget-3sg-aorist that Ivan like-sg-pap strawberries. Elena forgot that Ivan reportedly likes strawberries. Assume a different context: Elena is again making a cake for Ivan, and consults me again, but now I only have hearsay information about what Ivan likes. Then (14) is felicitous. 18 / 35

Structure: (Non) embedability and the speaker oriented nature of the reportative. Implications of being speaker oriented (the reportative is a Conventional Implicature [Potts(2005)]). An analysis: The reportative and weak assertions: the idea of kernels in [von Fintel and Gillies(2010)]. The reportative as a non commitment device :the discourse structure in [Farkas and Bruce(2010)]. 19 / 35

von Fintel and Gillies Kernels [von Fintel and Gillies(2010)]: an alternative analysis of epistemic must: Sentences containing epistemic must are not really weak. Instead, they contain a presupposition that the evidence on which the proposition is based is indirect (i.e., requires inference). A kernel is a set of privileged ( direct enough ) propositions. must p is used when the kernel entails but does not directly settle p. Intuition: K (the kernel) can entail p without settling it. Two ways of implementing settles p. The simpler one: K c directly settles whether p iff for some q P K c either: q entails p (q p) or q entails p (q X p m) I define positively settles as entailing p: K c positively settles whether p iff for some q P K c q p. 20 / 35

von Fintel and Gillies Kernels B k, the base for the kernel K is defined as B K XK (meaning B K tw @p P K : ppw q 1u) must is defined as follows, for a fixed c-relevant kernel K c : 1. vmustφw c,w is defined only if K c does not directly settle vφw c 2. vmustφw w,c 1 iff B k c vφw c (the Kernel entails φ) 21 / 35

The Reportative, Non-commitments and Kernels: Same line of analysis for the Bulgarian reportative: instead of involving an inference process, the secondary status is defined by a less reliable information source. A weak kernel for a speaker A in context c, WK A,c, is the set of all propositions for which the speaker has only evidence which he considers unreliable (such as hearing from someone non trustworthy). Intuitively, the reportative is used when p P WK A,c. Difference between p P WK A,c and saying that there is reported evidence for p: when there is only reported evidence for p, but the evidence source is trustworthy enough (for example, a history or science book), the speaker may choose to place p in the kernel, rather than in WK A,c. 22 / 35

The Reportative, Non-commitments and Kernels: A two part meaning: assertion: assert p CI: speaker is not committed to p Define a basic knowledge set for an agent A in context c to consist of the two kernels (the kernel and the weak kernel), and exclude all deductions. The basic knowledge set only includes propositions which are either positively settled by the kernel or the weak kernel (The weak kernel positively settles p iff for some q P WK A,c q entails p). BKS A,c, the basic knowledge set for an agent A in context c is defined as follows: 1. if p is positively settled by K A,c then p P BKS A,c 2. if p is positively settled by WK A,c then p P BKS A,c 3. nothing else is in BKS A,c 23 / 35

The Reportative, Non-commitments and Kernels: For a fixed context c and a speaker A kernel K A,c and basic knowledge set BKS A,c, define the reportative as: rrrppqss A,c 1 iff 1. Assertion part: p P BKS A,c 2. Conventional implicature part: B k A,c p The first part amounts to p being something the speaker has either direct or reported evidence for, but excluding inferences. The second, CI part amounts to placing p in the set complement to the (strong) kernel and what is entailed by it. 24 / 35

The Reportative, Non-commitments and Kernels: The CI part is separate from the assertion part, thus in embedded cases the CI part can be about the proposition in the embedded clause, while the matrix clause gets asserted. It is always the matrix clause that is asserted, but the CI can be about the embedded clause. Let q be the proposition expressed by the entire utterance, and p the proposition corresponding to the embedded clause (in which the reportative is used). The meaning derived is: 1. Assertion part: B BKS q A,c 2. Conventional implicature part: B k p The assertion part is different than the one for the matrix clause. By default, if nothing further is specified about q, the hearer is free to assume that q is entailed by the (strong) kernel. Compatible with the fact that the reportative is optional. 25 / 35

Structure: (Non) embedability and the speaker oriented nature of the reportative. Implications of being speaker oriented (the reportative is a Conventional Implicature [Potts(2005)]). An analysis: The reportative and weak assertions: the idea of kernels in [von Fintel and Gillies(2010)]. The reportative as a non commitment device :the discourse structure in [Farkas and Bruce(2010)]. 26 / 35

Reportative Assertions: Hey, take that p back! Consider the following piece of discourse: (15) A: Ivan bil bolen Ivan is-sg-pap sick Ivan is reportedly sick (16) B: Ne e vjarno. Sega go vidjah i nikak ne Neg is-3sg-pres true. Now him see-1sg-aorist and not-at-all neg e bolen. is-3sg-pres sick (17) A: Taka So That is not true. I just saw him and he is not sick at all. li? E dobre, az samo taka čuh Q? Oh okay, I just that hear-1sg-aoris Is that right? Well okay, I only heard that. Using the reportative in (15) allows A to easily retract the statement. Conversational effect of the reportative: p, but I am willing to take it back, since I have weak evidence. 27 / 35

Farkas and Bruce s discourse structure A discourse structure K contains: A set of propositions for each participant, DC X : the propositions that X has publicly committed to in the conversation up to the relevant time, and to which the other speakers have not yet agreed. cg, a set of propositions, containing all propositions that have been confirmed by all speakers. A Table, used for recording the questions under discussion If an agent A asserts a proposition p: 1. Add p to the DC A 2. Update the table by adding p to the top. Another discourse participant B can accept p (by adding p to DC B ). If all discourse participants accept p, it is added to cg and removed from the table and from the DC sets of each participant. 28 / 35

Reportative Assertions: Hey, take that p back! Formalization in the current framework: make DC richer. Expand DC A to contain two sets of propositions (corresponding to the weak verses strong kernel distinction): the vouched for (strong) set DC A S, and the non vouched for (weak) set DC A W. If the speaker uses the reportative, p is added to DC A W, otherwise to DC A S. Add p to the top of the stack, since now it is the QUD. Each of the other discourse participants can add p to their DC ( to their DC W, they have no reason to make a stronger commitment than the person proposing p). If all speakers add p to their DC then p is added to cg. 29 / 35

Embedded Reportatives in Conversation Let q be the proposition expressed by the entire utterance, and p the proposition corresponding to the embedded clause (in which the reportative is used). Both p and q are added to the table and to DC X : p is added to DC W, and q to DC S Motivation for adding both: (18) A: Mary said that John is sick. (19) B: That s not true! Mary said no such thing/ John is not sick. q is added to DC S, since if speaker X did not bother with explicitly using the reportative in the matrix clause, he is taking responsibility for it. 30 / 35

Conclusion The reportative in Bulgarian is a CI rather than a presupposition, it can be syntactically but not semantically embedded. An analysis in terms of kernels, rather than modality. A sketch of a discourse analysis, as a non committing device. 31 / 35

Many thanks to my adviser Prof. Florian Schwarz! 32 / 35

Appendix: Other Usages of the Reportative and Open Issues The reportative morphology may be used to express surprise. Example: (20) Gledaj ti, Ivan bil tuk! See-imp you, Ivan is-sg-pap here Look, Ivan is here! (surprise) (20) is felicitous even if the speaker is standing right in front of Ivan, as long as the fact that Ivan is present is surprising. Are surprise usages speaker oriented? 33 / 35

Appendix: Other Usages of the Reportative and Open Issues Can be analyzed along the lines of the non commitment reportative and in the same framework. The surprise reportative can be used when the proposition expressed is unlikely given the other propositions in the speaker s kernel, but does not have an implication that the speaker is not committing. In other words, using the idea of thresholds in [Davis et al.(2007)] when the probability of p, given K A,c is lower than some contextually supplied threshold. 34 / 35

The Dubitative: and by p I mean p Used when the speaker expresses doubt, in addition to uncertainty about the proposition expressed. Formed by adding another be auxiliary, in the PAP. If such auxiliary is already present, nothing is added. (21) Ivan bil kupil nova k@šta Ivan is-sg-pap buy-pap-sg new house. Ivan reportedly bought a new house (but I doubt it) 35 / 35

The Dubitative: and by p I mean p Can connect the non commitment reportative and the surprise one: The speaker not wishing to commit to the proposition expressed The speaker signaling that furthermore, this proposition is unlikely, given what he knows (other propositions in kernel). The assertion part is like for the non commitment reportative, and the CI consists of two parts : the unlikelihood of p (the probability of p given the kernel being smaller than some constant), and p not being entailed by the kernel. Since the assertion is weak, there is no contradiction between asserting p and doubting p at the same time. Conversationally, the dubitative amounts to weakly asserting p and signaling that really, p is the case (since p is unlikely). 36 / 35

Davis, Christopher, Christopher Potts, and Margaret Speas. 2007. The Pragmatic Values of Evidential Sentences. Presented at SALT. Farkas, Donka F., and Kim B. Bruce. 2010. On Reacting to Assertions and Polar Questions. Journal of Semantics 27:81 118. von Fintel, Kai, and Anthony S. Gillies. 2010. Must... Stay... Strong! To appear in Natural Language Semantics. Izvorski, Romyana. 1997. The present perfect as an epistemic modal. Semantics and Linguistic Theory VII:222 239. Matthewson, Lisa, Henry Davis, and Hotze Rullmann. 2006. Evidentials as epistemic modals: evidence from St at imcets. Unpublished ms., University of British Columbia. Potts, Christopher. 2005. The Logic of Conventional Implicatures. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sauerland, Uli, and Mathias Schenner. 2007. Embedded Evidentials in Bulgarian. Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 11 495 509. 36 / 35