Argument structure and theta roles

Similar documents
Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

Hindi-Urdu Phrase Structure Annotation

Theoretical Syntax Winter Answers to practice problems

Control and Boundedness

Update on Soar-based language processing

Inleiding Taalkunde. Docent: Paola Monachesi. Blok 4, 2001/ Syntax 2. 2 Phrases and constituent structure 2. 3 A minigrammar of Italian 3

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Long-distance wh-movement. Long distance wh-movement. Islands. Islands. Locality. NP Sea. NP Sea

The subject of adjectives: Syntactic position and semantic interpretation

Agree or Move? On Partial Control Anna Snarska, Adam Mickiewicz University

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Construction Grammar. University of Jena.

CS 598 Natural Language Processing

The presence of interpretable but ungrammatical sentences corresponds to mismatches between interpretive and productive parsing.

Language acquisition: acquiring some aspects of syntax.

Korean ECM Constructions and Cyclic Linearization

Pseudo-Passives as Adjectival Passives

Chapter 4: Valence & Agreement CSLI Publications

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

Som and Optimality Theory

The Structure of Relative Clauses in Maay Maay By Elly Zimmer

Derivational: Inflectional: In a fit of rage the soldiers attacked them both that week, but lost the fight.

THE FU CTIO OF ACCUSATIVE CASE I MO GOLIA *

1/20 idea. We ll spend an extra hour on 1/21. based on assigned readings. so you ll be ready to discuss them in class

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

Syntax Parsing 1. Grammars and parsing 2. Top-down and bottom-up parsing 3. Chart parsers 4. Bottom-up chart parsing 5. The Earley Algorithm

Words come in categories

THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & SOCIAL STUDIES

Unaccusatives, Resultatives, and the Richness of Lexical Representations

Lexical Categories and the Projection of Argument Structure

The semantics of case *

Ch VI- SENTENCE PATTERNS.

Context Free Grammars. Many slides from Michael Collins

LIN 6520 Syntax 2 T 5-6, Th 6 CBD 234

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

Natural Language Processing. George Konidaris

ENGBG1 ENGBL1 Campus Linguistics. Meeting 2. Chapter 7 (Morphology) and chapter 9 (Syntax) Pia Sundqvist

Derivations (MP) and Evaluations (OT) *

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

Today we examine the distribution of infinitival clauses, which can be

SOME MINIMAL NOTES ON MINIMALISM *

LQVSumm: A Corpus of Linguistic Quality Violations in Multi-Document Summarization

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Type-driven semantic interpretation and feature dependencies in R-LFG

DIRECT AND INDIRECT SPEECH

On Labeling: Principle C and Head Movement

An Introduction to the Minimalist Program

Chapter 3: Semi-lexical categories. nor truly functional. As Corver and van Riemsdijk rightly point out, There is more

Developing a TT-MCTAG for German with an RCG-based Parser

5 Minimalism and Optimality Theory

IS THERE A PASSIVE IN DHOLUO?

Grammars & Parsing, Part 1:

California Department of Education English Language Development Standards for Grade 8

Compositional Semantics

Chapter 1 The functional approach to language and the typological approach to grammar

Phenomena of gender attraction in Polish *

Tibor Kiss Reconstituting Grammar: Hagit Borer's Exoskeletal Syntax 1

Second Language Acquisition of Complex Structures: The Case of English Restrictive Relative Clauses

L1 and L2 acquisition. Holger Diessel

The MEANING Multilingual Central Repository

Visual CP Representation of Knowledge

Second Language Acquisition of Korean Case by Learners with. Different First Languages

Focusing bound pronouns

Beyond constructions:

Dependency, licensing and the nature of grammatical relations *

THE INDONESIAN JOURNAL OF LANGUAGE AND LANGUAGE TEACHING

Part I. Figuring out how English works

VERB MEANINGS AND THEIR EFFECTS ON SYNTACTIC BEHAVIORS: A STUDY WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO ENGLISH AND JAPANESE ERGATIVE PAIRS

Chinese for Beginners CEFR Level: A1

cmp-lg/ Jul 1995

LNGT0101 Introduction to Linguistics

Sensitivity to second language argument structure

Copyright and moral rights for this thesis are retained by the author

Construction Grammar. Laura A. Michaelis.

LFG Semantics via Constraints

How to become passive. Berit Gehrke and Nino Grillo

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

Tagged for Deletion: A Typological Approach to VP Ellipsis in Tag Questions

Hindi Aspectual Verb Complexes

Some Principles of Automated Natural Language Information Extraction

Heads and history NIGEL VINCENT & KERSTI BÖRJARS The University of Manchester

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

Derivational and Inflectional Morphemes in Pak-Pak Language

PROBLEMS IN ADJUNCT CARTOGRAPHY: A CASE STUDY NG PEI FANG FACULTY OF LANGUAGES AND LINGUISTICS UNIVERSITY OF MALAYA KUALA LUMPUR

Set up your desk: Do Now Share-Out 1. Do Now Share-Out 2. Rule the World Essay 10/11/2012

Aspectual Classes of Verb Phrases

CX 101/201/301 Latin Language and Literature 2015/16

Citation for published version (APA): Veenstra, M. J. A. (1998). Formalizing the minimalist program Groningen: s.n.

Pye, C The Focus Antipassive in Quiché Mayan, Kansas University Working Papers in Linguistics.

18 The syntax phonology interface

The optimal placement of up and ab A comparison 1

Advanced Grammar in Use

The Syntax of Coordinate Structure Complexes

11/29/2010. Statistical Parsing. Statistical Parsing. Simple PCFG for ATIS English. Syntactic Disambiguation

Neural & Predictive Effects of Verb Argument Structure

Which verb classes and why? Research questions: Semantic Basis Hypothesis (SBH) What verb classes? Why the truth of the SBH matters

Transcription:

Argument structure and theta roles Introduction to Syntax, EGG Summer School 2017 András Bárány ab155@soas.ac.uk 26 July 2017

Overview Where we left off Arguments and theta roles Some consequences of theta theory Conclusions 2/27

where we left off Where we left off 3/27

where we left off Merge builds structure We saw yesterday that Merge builds syntactic structure (1) VP V kisses DP Jiři But Merge as we know it is too general: it overgenerates (2) a. *Mary snores Jiři. b. *Mary said. c. Mary kisses Jiři. (cf. Koeneman & Zeijlstra 2017: 55)? What causes this? 4/27

where we left off Constraining Merge We want Merge to be able to combine Vs and DPs or NPs, so how do we restrict it? Clearly, there is something about the verbs involved kiss is a? snore is a? say is a? 5/27

where we left off Constraining Merge We want Merge to be able to combine Vs and DPs or NPs, so how do we restrict it? Clearly, there is something about the verbs involved kiss is a? snore is a? say is a? These verbs have certain selectional requirements They need a fixed number of arguments (with specific features) Theta (θ) theory is one way of explaining this today s slides are based on Koeneman & Zeijlstra (2017: 3), Adger (2003: 3) 5/27

where we left off Verbs and their arguments snore is an intransitive verb It takes one (and just one) argument kiss is a (mono-)transitive verb It takes two arguments give is a ditransitive verb It takes three arguments (two objects)? What kinds of arguments do these verbs take? Syntax distinguishes types of verbs by how many arguments and what kinds of arguments they take. In other words, verbs select for certain arguments. 6/27

arguments and theta roles Arguments and theta roles 7/27

arguments and theta roles Arguments and adverbials How do we model these restrictions? First, what is an argument? (3) a. Mary gave Jiři a kiss. b. *Mary gave Jiři a kiss Milena. c. Mary gave Jiři a kiss yesterday. (4) a. Mary said she liked Jiři. b. Yesterday Mary said she liked Jiři. c. * Yesterday Mary said Ø. 8/27

arguments and theta roles Arguments and adverbials How do we model these restrictions? First, what is an argument? (3) a. Mary gave Jiři a kiss. b. *Mary gave Jiři a kiss Milena. c. Mary gave Jiři a kiss yesterday. (4) a. Mary said she liked Jiři. b. Yesterday Mary said she liked Jiři. c. * Yesterday Mary said Ø. We cannot add another DP to (3a). We can add a phrase like yesterday (3a). We cannot leave out the object in (4). 8/27

arguments and theta roles Arguments and adverbials II give and say have different requirements give takes two DPs as its objects say takes a CP (a complementiser phrase) as its object adverbials like yesterday can be added or removed freely adverbials are not selected for, but arguments are? What about Mary gave? 9/27

arguments and theta roles Theta roles Based on the number of its arguments, a verb assigns theta roles to them give expresses a relation between 1. someone who gives, 2. something being given, 3. someone receiving something kiss expresses a relation between 1. someone who kisses, 2. someone (or something!) being kissed To understand these verbs, we need these roles to be assigned and expressed Every argument must carry one theta role. Every theta role must be assigned to one argument. This is the theta-criterion 10/27

arguments and theta roles The theta criterion The theta criterion explains the ungrammaticality of too many/too few arguments? What about the following examples, however? (5) a. Anna is eating. b. Anna is eating a sandwich. (6) a. Jiři gave a book. b. Jiři gave Anna a book. (7) a. *Milena snored a sandwich. b. Milena snored yesterday. 11/27

arguments and theta roles The theta criterion The theta criterion explains the ungrammaticality of too many/too few arguments? What about the following examples, however? (5) a. Anna is eating. b. Anna is eating a sandwich. (6) a. Jiři gave a book. b. Jiři gave Anna a book. (7) a. *Milena snored a sandwich. b. Milena snored yesterday. Some differences boil down to lexical semantics: *Anna is saying. 11/27

arguments and theta roles Types of theta roles So what is actually assigned? Theta roles come in different flavours 12/27

arguments and theta roles Types of theta roles So what is actually assigned? Theta roles come in different flavours AGENT: an entity (willfully) doing something PATIENT/THEME: an (animate) entity undergoing something RECIPIENT/GOAL: an (animate) entity receiving something (8) The detective interrogates the suspect / the ball. (9) Mary loves the children / classical music. (10) a. Milena gave Jiři the book. b. Milena gave the book to the library. 12/27

arguments and theta roles Types of theta roles So what is actually assigned? Theta roles come in different flavours AGENT: an entity (willfully) doing something PATIENT/THEME: an (animate) entity undergoing something RECIPIENT/GOAL: an (animate) entity receiving something (8) The detective interrogates the suspect / the ball. (9) Mary loves the children / classical music. (10) a. Milena gave Jiři the book. b. Milena gave the book to the library. 12/27

arguments and theta roles Types of theta roles So what is actually assigned? Theta roles come in different flavours AGENT: an entity (willfully) doing something PATIENT/THEME: an (animate) entity undergoing something RECIPIENT/GOAL: an (animate) entity receiving something (8) The detective interrogates the suspect / the ball. (9) Mary loves the children / classical music. (10) a. Milena gave Jiři the book. b. Milena gave the book to the library. 12/27

arguments and theta roles Other types of verbs Verbs do not just differ in the number of theta roles they assign subjects are often AGENTS (direct) objects are often PATIENTS/THEMES but this is not always the case! (11) a. Jiři fell. b. The glass broke. c. The cat died. d. Milena is baking. e. The government armed the people.? How can we test for this? 13/27

arguments and theta roles Regularities in theta roles When a verb takes a single argument, i.e. it is intransitive, it can take an AGENT or a PATIENT/THEME When a verb takes two arguments, i.e. it is (mono)transitive, it can take an AGENT subject and a PATIENT/THEME object an AGENT subject and a RECIPIENT object a RECIPIENT subject and a THEME object an EXPERIENCER subject and a THEME object But certain mappings of theta roles onto arguments are ruled out! no verb assigns PATIENT to the subject and AGENT to the object 14/27

arguments and theta roles The theta hierarchy This motivates a first distinction on the theta hierarchy (12) AGENT > PATIENT/THEME Koeneman & Zeijlstra (2017) argue for extending the hierarchy using (13) (13) a. Jiři AGENT b. *Jiři AGENT gave Anna RECIPIENT gave a book THEME a book. THEME Anna. RECIPIENT 15/27

arguments and theta roles The theta hierarchy This motivates a first distinction on the theta hierarchy (12) AGENT > RECIPIENT > PATIENT/THEME Koeneman & Zeijlstra (2017) argue for extending the hierarchy using (13) (13) a. Jiři AGENT b. *Jiři AGENT gave Anna RECIPIENT gave a book THEME a book. THEME Anna. RECIPIENT 15/27

arguments and theta roles The theta hierarchy This motivates a first distinction on the theta hierarchy (12) AGENT > RECIPIENT > PATIENT/THEME > GOAL Koeneman & Zeijlstra (2017) argue for extending the hierarchy using (13) (13) a. Jiři AGENT b. *Jiři AGENT gave Anna RECIPIENT gave a book THEME a book. THEME Anna. RECIPIENT 15/27

arguments and theta roles The theta hierarchy This motivates a first distinction on the theta hierarchy (12) AGENT > RECIPIENT > PATIENT/THEME > GOAL Koeneman & Zeijlstra (2017) argue for extending the hierarchy using (13) (13) a. Jiři AGENT b. *Jiři AGENT gave Anna RECIPIENT gave a book THEME a book. THEME Anna. RECIPIENT (13) suggests that there are verbs which take a RECIPIENT and a THEME argument? Can you think of such verbs? 15/27

arguments and theta roles Interim summary Verbs select for a certain number of arguments and certain types of arguments: theta roles theta roles are mapped onto arguments in certain ways subjects are often AGENTS, objects are often PATIENTS, etc. looking at these mappings motivates the theta hierarchy (there is some other evidence for it, too) 16/27

some consequences of theta theory Some consequences of theta theory 17/27

some consequences of theta theory The number of arguments and grammatical functions Any verb, independently of the number of its arguments, seems to have a subject If a verb takes a single argument, it is always a subject. (14) a. Mary kisses John. b. *Kisses John. c. John is kissed. It is then tempting to make a stronger generalisation about subjects (15) Every sentence has a subject. (Koeneman & Zeijlstra 2017: 68)? What about Swim! or It is raining? 18/27

some consequences of theta theory Accusative, ergative, unaccusative, and unergative verbs Some more evidence for a theta hierarchy comes from different types of verbs ergative verbs can be transitive and intransitive (see (16)) accusative verbs can also be transitive or intransitive (see (17)) The two types differ in the theta role they assign when intransitive: (16) a. The butter is melting. (17) a. Mary is eating. 19/27

some consequences of theta theory Accusative, ergative, unaccusative, and unergative verbs Some more evidence for a theta hierarchy comes from different types of verbs ergative verbs can be transitive and intransitive (see (16)) accusative verbs can also be transitive or intransitive (see (17)) The two types differ in the theta role they assign when intransitive: (16) a. The butter is melting. b. Mary is melting the butter. (17) a. Mary is eating. 19/27

some consequences of theta theory Accusative, ergative, unaccusative, and unergative verbs Some more evidence for a theta hierarchy comes from different types of verbs ergative verbs can be transitive and intransitive (see (16)) accusative verbs can also be transitive or intransitive (see (17)) The two types differ in the theta role they assign when intransitive: (16) a. The butter is melting. PATIENT b. Mary is melting the butter. AGENT, PATIENT (17) a. Mary is eating. 19/27

some consequences of theta theory Accusative, ergative, unaccusative, and unergative verbs Some more evidence for a theta hierarchy comes from different types of verbs ergative verbs can be transitive and intransitive (see (16)) accusative verbs can also be transitive or intransitive (see (17)) The two types differ in the theta role they assign when intransitive: (16) a. The butter is melting. b. Mary is melting the butter. (17) a. Mary is eating. b. Mary is eating a sandwich. 19/27

some consequences of theta theory Accusative, ergative, unaccusative, and unergative verbs Some more evidence for a theta hierarchy comes from different types of verbs ergative verbs can be transitive and intransitive (see (16)) accusative verbs can also be transitive or intransitive (see (17)) The two types differ in the theta role they assign when intransitive: (16) a. The butter is melting. b. Mary is melting the butter. (17) a. Mary is eating. AGENT b. Mary is eating a sandwich. AGENT, PATIENT 19/27

some consequences of theta theory Accusative, ergative, unaccusative, and unergative verbs Some more evidence for a theta hierarchy comes from different types of verbs ergative verbs can be transitive and intransitive (see (16)) accusative verbs can also be transitive or intransitive (see (17)) The two types differ in the theta role they assign when intransitive: (16) a. The butter is melting. PATIENT b. Mary is melting the butter. AGENT, PATIENT (17) a. Mary is eating. AGENT b. Mary is eating a sandwich. AGENT, PATIENT 19/27

some consequences of theta theory Theta roles as diagnostics for structure We have seen that verbs have particular requirements on what they combine with This helps us diagnose differences between structures which look identical (18) a. John hopes [ to win the race ]. b. John seems [ to win the race ]. Both (18a,b) consist of a main clause and an embedded clause Both sentences have John as their subjects? Are they identical structurally and semantically? 20/27

some consequences of theta theory Theta roles as diagnostics for structure II (19) a. John hopes [ to win the race ]. b. John seems [ to win the race ].? How many and which theta roles do hope and win assign? 21/27

some consequences of theta theory Theta roles as diagnostics for structure II (19) a. John hopes [ to win the race ]. b. John seems [ to win the race ].? How many and which theta roles do hope and win assign? hope: AGENT, THEME win: AGENT, THEME 21/27

some consequences of theta theory Theta roles as diagnostics for structure II (19) a. John hopes [ to win the race ]. b. John seems [ to win the race ].? How many and which theta roles do hope and win assign? hope: AGENT, THEME win: AGENT, THEME? How many and which theta roles do seem and win assign? 21/27

some consequences of theta theory Theta roles as diagnostics for structure II (19) a. John hopes [ to win the race ]. b. John seems [ to win the race ].? How many and which theta roles do hope and win assign? hope: AGENT, THEME win: AGENT, THEME? How many and which theta roles do seem and win assign? seem: THEME win: AGENT, THEME 21/27

some consequences of theta theory Raising vs. control The two examples in (19a,b) illustrate the difference between control and raising In control, a special type of pronoun, PRO gets the embedded AGENT role Both the main verb and the embedded verb assign AGENT theta roles AGENT THEME (20) John i hopes [ PRO i to win the race ]. 22/27

some consequences of theta theory Raising vs. control The two examples in (19a,b) illustrate the difference between control and raising In control, a special type of pronoun, PRO gets the embedded AGENT role Both the main verb and the embedded verb assign AGENT theta roles AGENT THEME (20) John i hopes [ PRO i to win the race ]. AGENT THEME 22/27

some consequences of theta theory Raising vs. control The two examples in (19a,b) illustrate the difference between control and raising In control, a special type of pronoun, PRO gets the embedded AGENT role Both the main verb and the embedded verb assign AGENT theta roles AGENT THEME (20) John i hopes [ PRO i to win the race ]. AGENT THEME In raising, the main clause subject is not assigned a theta role by seem (21) John i seems [ i to win the race ]. THEME 22/27

some consequences of theta theory Raising vs. control The two examples in (19a,b) illustrate the difference between control and raising In control, a special type of pronoun, PRO gets the embedded AGENT role Both the main verb and the embedded verb assign AGENT theta roles AGENT THEME (20) John i hopes [ PRO i to win the race ]. AGENT THEME In raising, the main clause subject is not assigned a theta role by seem AGENT THEME (21) John i seems [ John i to win the race ]. THEME 22/27

some consequences of theta theory Raising vs. control The two examples in (19a,b) illustrate the difference between control and raising In control, a special type of pronoun, PRO gets the embedded AGENT role Both the main verb and the embedded verb assign AGENT theta roles AGENT THEME (20) John i hopes [ PRO i to win the race ]. AGENT THEME In raising, the main clause subject is not assigned a theta role by seem AGENT (21) John i seems [ John i to win the race ]. THEME 22/27

some consequences of theta theory Raising vs. control II Can we confirm that seems does not assign a theta role to its subject? 23/27

some consequences of theta theory Raising vs. control II Can we confirm that seems does not assign a theta role to its subject? (22) a. It seems that John is winning the race. b. *It hopes that John is winning the race. The theta criterion assigns different structures to raising and control? Is this the only possibility?? What kind of element is PRO? How is it restricted? 23/27

some consequences of theta theory Merge, arguments and adjuncts We can combine what we ve said so far with what we learned about Merge. A lexical item s argument structure can be represented by features Such features are called c-selectional or subcategorisation features below, they are shown as ux where u means uninterpretable These features are checked off when they are matched (23) XP (24) VP (25) VP X[uF] Y[F] kiss [un] John [N] become [V, ua] fond [A, up] AP of [P, un] PP Lloyd [N] 24/27

some consequences of theta theory Merge, arguments and adjuncts We can combine what we ve said so far with what we learned about Merge. A lexical item s argument structure can be represented by features Such features are called c-selectional or subcategorisation features below, they are shown as ux where u means uninterpretable These features are checked off when they are matched (23) XP (24) VP (25) VP X[uF] Y[F] kiss [un] John [N] become [V, ua] fond [A, up] AP of [P, un] PP Lloyd [N] 24/27

some consequences of theta theory Merge, arguments and adjuncts We can combine what we ve said so far with what we learned about Merge. A lexical item s argument structure can be represented by features Such features are called c-selectional or subcategorisation features below, they are shown as ux where u means uninterpretable These features are checked off when they are matched (23) XP (24) VP (25) VP X[uF] Y[F] kiss [un] John [N] become [V, ua] fond [A, up] AP of [P, un] PP Lloyd [N] 24/27

some consequences of theta theory Merge, arguments and adjuncts We can combine what we ve said so far with what we learned about Merge. A lexical item s argument structure can be represented by features Such features are called c-selectional or subcategorisation features below, they are shown as ux where u means uninterpretable These features are checked off when they are matched (23) XP (24) VP (25) VP X[uF] Y[F] kiss [un] John [N] become [V, ua] fond [A, up] AP of [P, un] PP Lloyd [N] 24/27

some consequences of theta theory Merge, arguments and adjuncts We can combine what we ve said so far with what we learned about Merge. A lexical item s argument structure can be represented by features Such features are called c-selectional or subcategorisation features below, they are shown as ux where u means uninterpretable These features are checked off when they are matched (23) XP (24) VP (25) VP X[uF] Y[F] kiss [un] John [N] become [V, ua] fond [A, up] AP of [P, un] PP Lloyd [N] 24/27

some consequences of theta theory Merge, arguments and adjuncts We can combine what we ve said so far with what we learned about Merge. A lexical item s argument structure can be represented by features Such features are called c-selectional or subcategorisation features below, they are shown as ux where u means uninterpretable These features are checked off when they are matched (23) XP (24) VP (25) VP X[uF] Y[F] kiss [un] John [N] become [V, ua] fond [A, up] AP of [P, un] PP Lloyd [N] 24/27

some consequences of theta theory Merge, arguments and adjuncts We can combine what we ve said so far with what we learned about Merge. A lexical item s argument structure can be represented by features Such features are called c-selectional or subcategorisation features below, they are shown as ux where u means uninterpretable These features are checked off when they are matched (23) XP (24) VP (25) VP X[uF] Y[F] kiss [un] John [N] become [V, ua] fond [A, up] AP of [P, un] PP Lloyd [N] 24/27

some consequences of theta theory Merge, arguments and adjuncts We can combine what we ve said so far with what we learned about Merge. A lexical item s argument structure can be represented by features Such features are called c-selectional or subcategorisation features below, they are shown as ux where u means uninterpretable These features are checked off when they are matched (23) XP (24) VP (25) VP X[uF] Y[F] kiss [un] John [N] become [V, ua] fond [A, up] AP of [P, un] PP Lloyd [N] 24/27

conclusions Conclusions 25/27

conclusions Conclusions Lexical items have selectional requirements On verbs, these include specific theta roles Verbs can also select for semantic features like animacy s-selection Verbs, and other items also select for certain categories c-selection c-selection restricts Merge and builds grammatical structures Tomorrow we will look at case theory: what is case and what role does it play in syntax? 26/27

conclusions References I Adger, David. 2003. Core syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Koeneman, Olaf & Hedde Zeijlstra. 2017. Introducing syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 27/27