DRT s treatment of inference and presupposition as a source of semantic enrichment

Similar documents
Proof Theory for Syntacticians

Segmented Discourse Representation Theory. Dynamic Semantics with Discourse Structure

Specifying Logic Programs in Controlled Natural Language

Some Principles of Automated Natural Language Information Extraction

ELD CELDT 5 EDGE Level C Curriculum Guide LANGUAGE DEVELOPMENT VOCABULARY COMMON WRITING PROJECT. ToolKit

Frequency and pragmatically unmarked word order *

Universal Grammar 2. Universal Grammar 1. Forms and functions 1. Universal Grammar 3. Conceptual and surface structure of complex clauses

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Links, tails and monotonicity

Intra-talker Variation: Audience Design Factors Affecting Lexical Selections

AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO NEW AND OLD INFORMATION IN TURKISH LOCATIVES AND EXISTENTIALS

Replies to Greco and Turner

Approaches to control phenomena handout Obligatory control and morphological case: Icelandic and Basque

Lecture 9. The Semantic Typology of Indefinites

Informatics 2A: Language Complexity and the. Inf2A: Chomsky Hierarchy

Objectives. Chapter 2: The Representation of Knowledge. Expert Systems: Principles and Programming, Fourth Edition

CEFR Overall Illustrative English Proficiency Scales

Inleiding Taalkunde. Docent: Paola Monachesi. Blok 4, 2001/ Syntax 2. 2 Phrases and constituent structure 2. 3 A minigrammar of Italian 3

An Approach to Polarity Sensitivity and Negative Concord by Lexical Underspecification

Introduction to HPSG. Introduction. Historical Overview. The HPSG architecture. Signature. Linguistic Objects. Descriptions.

Aspectual Classes of Verb Phrases

Compositional Semantics

ENGBG1 ENGBL1 Campus Linguistics. Meeting 2. Chapter 7 (Morphology) and chapter 9 (Syntax) Pia Sundqvist

Case government vs Case agreement: modelling Modern Greek case attraction phenomena in LFG

Word Stress and Intonation: Introduction

Underlying and Surface Grammatical Relations in Greek consider

Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

Constraining X-Bar: Theta Theory

The College Board Redesigned SAT Grade 12

LFG Semantics via Constraints

Propositional Anaphora in English: The relationship between so and discourse

Unit 8 Pronoun References

Language Acquisition Chart

THE ANTINOMY OF THE VARIABLE: A TARSKIAN RESOLUTION Bryan Pickel and Brian Rabern University of Edinburgh

Specification and Evaluation of Machine Translation Toy Systems - Criteria for laboratory assignments

Constraints on metalinguistic anaphora

An Introduction to the Minimalist Program

cambridge occasional papers in linguistics Volume 8, Article 3: 41 55, 2015 ISSN

Abstractions and the Brain

Rule-based Expert Systems

Procedural pragmatics and the study of discourse Louis de Saussure

Metadiscourse in Knowledge Building: A question about written or verbal metadiscourse

Reading Grammar Section and Lesson Writing Chapter and Lesson Identify a purpose for reading W1-LO; W2- LO; W3- LO; W4- LO; W5-

5 th Grade Language Arts Curriculum Map

Routledge Library Editions: The English Language: Pronouns And Word Order In Old English: With Particular Reference To The Indefinite Pronoun Man

Strategic discourse comprehension

Minimalism is the name of the predominant approach in generative linguistics today. It was first

Information Structure and Referential Givenness/Newness: How Much Belongs in the Grammar?

CONTENUTI DEL CORSO (presentazione di disciplina, argomenti, programma):

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 154 ( 2014 )

Integrating Meta-Level and Domain-Level Knowledge for Task-Oriented Dialogue

Discourse markers and grammaticalization

Derivational and Inflectional Morphemes in Pak-Pak Language

On the Notion Determiner

Types and Lexical Semantics

Transitive meanings for intransitive verbs

Annotating (Anaphoric) Ambiguity 1 INTRODUCTION. Paper presentend at Corpus Linguistics 2005, University of Birmingham, England

Loughton School s curriculum evening. 28 th February 2017

An Interactive Intelligent Language Tutor Over The Internet

Applications of memory-based natural language processing

Beyond constructions:

The presence of interpretable but ungrammatical sentences corresponds to mismatches between interpretive and productive parsing.

ELA/ELD Standards Correlation Matrix for ELD Materials Grade 1 Reading

1/20 idea. We ll spend an extra hour on 1/21. based on assigned readings. so you ll be ready to discuss them in class

Multiple case assignment and the English pseudo-passive *

FOREWORD.. 5 THE PROPER RUSSIAN PRONUNCIATION. 8. УРОК (Unit) УРОК (Unit) УРОК (Unit) УРОК (Unit) 4 80.

Possessive have and (have) got in New Zealand English Heidi Quinn, University of Canterbury, New Zealand

L1 and L2 acquisition. Holger Diessel

Intermediate Academic Writing

GERM 3040 GERMAN GRAMMAR AND COMPOSITION SPRING 2017

Basic Syntax. Doug Arnold We review some basic grammatical ideas and terminology, and look at some common constructions in English.

PAGE(S) WHERE TAUGHT If sub mission ins not a book, cite appropriate location(s))

CELTA. Syllabus and Assessment Guidelines. Third Edition. University of Cambridge ESOL Examinations 1 Hills Road Cambridge CB1 2EU United Kingdom

Intension, Attitude, and Tense Annotation in a High-Fidelity Semantic Representation

Parsing of part-of-speech tagged Assamese Texts

Module 12. Machine Learning. Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

First Grade Curriculum Highlights: In alignment with the Common Core Standards

THE INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HUMANITIES & SOCIAL STUDIES

The Effect of Extensive Reading on Developing the Grammatical. Accuracy of the EFL Freshmen at Al Al-Bayt University

The Effect of Discourse Markers on the Speaking Production of EFL Students. Iman Moradimanesh

Blended Learning Module Design Template

Think A F R I C A when assessing speaking. C.E.F.R. Oral Assessment Criteria. Think A F R I C A - 1 -

Ontological spine, localization and multilingual access

THE SHORT ANSWER: IMPLICATIONS FOR DIRECT COMPOSITIONALITY (AND VICE VERSA) Pauline Jacobson. Brown University

TAG QUESTIONS" Department of Language and Literature - University of Birmingham

LING 329 : MORPHOLOGY

IMPROVING SPEAKING SKILL OF THE TENTH GRADE STUDENTS OF SMK 17 AGUSTUS 1945 MUNCAR THROUGH DIRECT PRACTICE WITH THE NATIVE SPEAKER

Context-Sensitive Bidirectional OT: a New Approach to Russian Aspect

Rubric for Scoring English 1 Unit 1, Rhetorical Analysis

Gricean Communication and Transmission of Thoughts

Written by: YULI AMRIA (RRA1B210085) ABSTRACT. Key words: ability, possessive pronouns, and possessive adjectives INTRODUCTION

SEMAFOR: Frame Argument Resolution with Log-Linear Models

Formulaic Language and Fluency: ESL Teaching Applications

Realization of Textual Cohesion and Coherence in Business Letters through Presupposition 1

Progressive Aspect in Nigerian English

Grade 4. Common Core Adoption Process. (Unpacked Standards)

Interactive Corpus Annotation of Anaphor Using NLP Algorithms

Control and Boundedness

Agree or Move? On Partial Control Anna Snarska, Adam Mickiewicz University

- «Crede Experto:,,,». 2 (09) ( '36

Transcription:

DRT s treatment of inference and presupposition as a source of semantic enrichment Francisco J. Salguero Lamillar Universidad de Sevilla salguero@cica.es 1 Inferential semantic enrichment in discourse interpretation The Discourse Representation Theory (DRT) (Kamp & Reyle 1993) provides an explanation of the semantic enrichment processes that are present in discourse, by means of the structure of the successive representations associated to a concrete sequence of utterances. In the case of pronominal anaphora or indefinites, interpretation is just possible in relation with those elements present in discourse or in associated databases. Each Discourse Representation Structure (DRS) can be seen as a database within which certain information about the world is codified. So, when the speaker codifies a message, we can think on a selection of lexical elements suitable for representing the referred individuals and the properties they have, the relations they hold in a concrete description of the world and even the properties and relations between this description of the world and other ones. All these elements are combined using certain rules; so the hearer obtains from the speaker a series of linguistic data to which he must apply his grammatical, logical and encyclopaedic knowledge in order to be able of decodifying the complete information. In a very general way, the following scheme could be an illustration of discourse interpretation process: Rules of grammar Rules of logic Knowledge of the world Discourse interpretation Figure 1 Grammar, logic and encyclopaedic knowledge appear in this scheme as separate modules with a unique and final relation: the interpretation of the speaker utterances. Nevertheless, there are enough reasons to think that the established relations among these modules are closer. Without discussing questions about syntactic or morphological iconicity and those logical aspects that are more evident in natural language grammar, we can consider 279

that the interpretation of any linguistic utterance rests on the application of all these knowledge modules to the intermediate representations of discourse that are necessary for evaluating the speaker utterances. Consider the scheme in Figure 2, more complex than the former one: Rules of Grammar (Linguistic Knowledge) Rules of Logic Meaning postulates Rules of lexical information Situation & Context (Knowledge of the world) Anaphoric variable instantiation rules Discourse (Previous information) Utterance Interpretation Figure 2 As it can be seen, the instantiation of anaphoric variables is considered as an intermediate module for the interpretation of utterances. Therefore, the interpretation of anaphora (pronouns, indefinite noun phrases, definite descriptions, relative clauses, spatial or temporal deictic terms, tense and aspect of verbs, etc.) is the common element for the confluence of the other modules. Hence the importance of anaphoric inference in DRT and another dynamic frames of discourse interpretation. In the interpretation of discourse, it is rare to have a unique database for establishing its global meaning. Several related databases are usually needed to obtain a model. The given relations among representations or necessary databases for the evaluation of discourse utterances are far away from those in classical model theory. Conceived in this manner as linguistic databases, the different representations of discourse are similar to possible worlds. So they can be seen as moments, giving a temporal interpretation to discourse representations; or they can be seen as successive states of the speaker/hearer s mind, and then we have that discourse representations are similar to Kripke s information states. Whatever the case could be, the representations of discourse are interpreted as partial models of reality, and therefore they can be treated as Hintikka sets (Salguero 1994). This perspective allows us dealing with discourse interpretation as a sort of logical calculus, a series of inferences on the successive representations of discourse that take the 280

hearer to the meaning of its constituent utterances. Such inferences depend on the rules of the grammatical and logical modules, and on the hearer s knowledge of the world. But there is even another decisive factor that intervenes in these inferences: presuppositions. 2 Presuppositions and DRT The notion of presupposition has been discussed since Antiquity, without having reached a consensus about its linguistic or logical nature up to the day. We can see it as a semantic relation between sentences and define it saying that a sentence B presupposes another sentence A if A implies B or if the truth value of A is a condition for the truth value of B. It is also usual to understand the notion of presupposition pragmatically as a set of attitudes and notices, being used by language users in their speech acts. In this case, we refer to speaker/hearer s presuppositions instead of sentence presuppositions. But there is no opposition between these two perspectives because we can treat presupposition as a one more part of the interpretation of the utterances that constitute discourse in a concrete representation of its meaning, and then both perspectives are satisfied: the semantic and the pragmatic one. This signifies that we will not find a well defined notion of presupposition in the specialised literature, but a set of linguistic data that must be explained in a theory about discourse interpretation (Levinson 1983). Typical examples of these linguistic data are sentences like: (1) Have you stopped hitting your wife? (2) The actual king of France is not bald In (1) we have that the verbal aspect and the possessive your presuppose that the hearer has a wife and that he hits her. In (2) we are in front of a classical existence presupposition introduced by the definite determiner the. Both sentences are classical examples of presuppositions, but they are not the only ones. We can classify the linguistic elements that can be the source of presuppositions in discourse, following (Beaver 1997): 1. Definite noun phrases, introduced by the definite article, demonstratives or possessives, proper names or even relative clauses. 2. Quantified noun phrases, introduced by a quantificational determiner. 3. Factive verbs or verbal nouns and noun phrases related to them, such as reject, know, the fact that, the acquaintance of, etc. In this case we can distinguish between cognitive factives, related to the knowledge of the facts, and emotive factives, related to emotional attitudes towards the facts. 4. Clefts (it-, wh- or pseudo-clefts), like It was not John who called you up, presupposing someone called you up. 5. Wh-questions that presuppose the existence of an entity suitable for an answer, like What colour is the snark?, presupposing the existence of a snark. 6. Counterfactuals, presupposing the falsity of the antecedent. 7. Lexical presuppositions. For instance, dog presupposes animal. 8. Action verbs, like stop doing something, aspectual or temporal modifiers, like before or after in certain sentences (v. gr.: After having your breakfast, go out to school, presupposing you are having breakfast). 281

9. Iterative expressions, like again, or the prefix re-, presupposing some kind of repetition. 10. Some discourse connectives, like although, but, because. Casuistry is wide and we do not pretend to have a list with every source of presupposition in discourse. But we can see now that presuppositions in the sentences (1) and (2) depend on verbal aspect and tense, studied, for instance, in (Kamp & Reyle 1993:483f.), and on the interpretation of noun phrases and the quantificational scope of the determiners. This last one is the most usual source of existential presupposition in discourse and we will analyse it in this paper. 2.1 Accommodation of presuppositions in DRSs It is evident, as we have mentioned before, that presuppositions play an important role in discourse interpretation. They are indeed a part in the semantic and logical structure of the discourse utterances and, therefore, they must appear in any representation of that structure. So we need a method for making presuppositions explicit in Discourse Representation Structures (DRSs), since they are the way in which DRT represents discourse interpretation. We are adopting van der Sandt s method, consisting in the explicit extension of discourse context in order to include in the correspondent DRS all the presuppositions intervening in the interpretation of the utterances (van der Sandt 1992, 1993). This method is called accommodation. Accommodation consists in the addition of discourse referents and conditions to a DRS. This addition is made in any of the accessible representations that contain the discourse element that triggers the presupposition. When a trigger element causes a presupposition without an antecedent, accommodation will consist in the transference of discourse markers and conditions of the presupposition from the representation of the trigger to an accessible DRS. Therefore, we can distinguish among local accommodation (when the addition is made in the same DRS of the trigger), global accommodation (when the addition is made in the main DRS that includes all the other representations), and intermediate accommodation (when the addition is made in another DRS, different from the main one and accessible from the DRS where the trigger element appears) (van der Sandt 1992). Triggers are seen as anaphoric elements in discourse interpretation because these elements cannot be interpreted with independence of the structural relation established between the position in which they are represented in a DRS and the place where the representations of their antecedents are: an accessible DRS, like in the case of pronominal anaphora s antecedents. Let us see an example taken from (Beaver 1997): (3) Mary doesn t realise that somebody is escaping. The correspondent DRS (DRS1) includes the presupposition somebody is escaping, that will be represented within a double line box. This presupposition marks the existence in the discourse universe of an individual z and verifies the condition is_escaping(z). The marker w can be instantiated as z because the presupposition is accessible from its DRS. We can compare (DRS1) with the interpretation of the sentence (4), represented by (DRS2): (4) Fred is escaping but Mary doesn t realise somebody is escaping. 282

(DRS1) y Mary(y) z is_escaping(z) w realises(y, is_escaping(w) ) (DRS2) x,y Fred(x) is_escaping(x) Mary(y) z is_escaping(z) w realises(y, is_escaping(w) ) The main DRS in (DRS2) is accessible from the negated DRS, so the marker z can be instantiated by means of the marker x. Therefore, the universe of the presupposition can be 283

reached from the global universe of discourse, as the condition of the presupposition is accessible like a global condition. This means that the presupposition has an antecedent and, therefore, as it does not play another role in (DRS2), it could be eliminated salva interpretatione. When we eliminate a presupposition by means of its resolution into an antecedent as in (DRS2), or when we accommodate it into a DRS accessible from the trigger s representation, we say that the presupposition is cancelled. But, how does the accommodation method work in relation with the presuppositions in a DRS? Consider the following sentence: (5) If Mary chose the Sherry then she realises it is a good wine. In the following DRSs, we will simplify the discourse markers using individual constants m and s, denoting Mary and Sherry respectively, and the bidimensional structure will be represented linearly for saving space in the page. Then, in (DRS3) the signs [ and ] are single line box limits and the signs { and } are double line box limits. An empty box [ ] means that there is no individual marker for that representation. (DRS3) [ [m,s] [ [ ] chose(m,s)] [ [ ] { [ ] good_wine(s) } realises(m, [ [ ] good_wine(s) ] ) ] ] In order to have a DRS where no presupposition appears without an antecedent, we must move the DRS representing the presupposition towards any of the sites that are accessible from the trigger s DRS, that is to say: from the representation of the sentence Mary realises that the Sherry is a good wine. This movement produces three different DRSs depending on the accommodation type: Global accommodation: The Sherry is a good wine and if Mary chose it, she realises it is a good wine. (DRS4) [ [m,s] good_wine(s) [ [ ] chose(m,s)] [ [ ] realises(m, [ [ ] good_wine(s) ] ) ] ] Intermediate accommodation: If the Sherry is a good wine and Mary chose it then she realises it is a good wine (DRS5) [ [m,s] [ [ ] good_wine(s) chose(m,s)] [ [ ] realises(m, [ [ ] good_wine(s) ] ) ] ] Local accommodation: If Mary chose the Sherry then it is a good wine and she realises it is a good wine. (DRS6) [ [m,s] [ [ ] chose(m,s)] [ [ ] good_wine(s) realises(m, [ [ ] good_wine(s) ] ) ] ] Each one of these three DRSs supposes a different interpretation of the existing relation between the sentence (5) and the presupposed sentence The Sherry is a good wine. Now we can ask what kind of accommodation is the best one for the interpretation of an uterrance like (5) and try to establish a priority. First, we must try to instantiate the presupposition markers in the actual accommodation. That is what is called resolution. But resolution is possible only when we have accessible markers for the instantiation, from the DRS containing the presupposition trigger up to the main DRS. When we cannot find markers for the resolution then we must appeal to accommodation, but now going in the reverse way: 284

from the main DRS up to the trigger s DRS. This means the priority is resolution and then, when resolution is not possible, global accommodation, intermediate accommodation and finally local accommodation. This process has certain constraints that can be found in (van der Sandt 1992) or in (Beaver 1997). 2.2 Existential presuppositions and DRSs We can now recover the classical example by Bertrand Russell to illustrate the treatment of existence presuppositions in DRT: (2) The actual king of France is not bald The problem for Predicate Logic is whether this sentence is true or false because there is no entity in the domain of discourse that could be considered as a good instantiation for the individual variable in order to satisfy the predicate to_be_the_king_of_france. Nevertheless, Russell said that the logical form of this sentence presupposes the existence of such an individual: [2] x(king_of_france(x) bald(x)) It is evident that if [2] is true then we can infer [2 ], that is to say: There is a king of France; but if [2] is false then we can infer [2 ], that is to say: All the kings of France are bald. [2 ] x(king_of_france(x)) [2 ] x(king_of_france(x) bald(x)), To avoid this kind of undesirable presuppositions, Russell proposed his theory of definite descriptions, introducing a logical operator as a descriptor. In this theory, two possible scopes were postulated for negation: a restricted scope [2*] (corresponding to the global accommodation of the presupposition) and a general scope [2 + ] (corresponding to the local accommodation): [2*] x[king_of_france(x)]( bald(x)) [2 + ] ( x[king_of_france(x)](bald(x))) (DRS7) Global accommodation: (DRS8) Local accommodation: x king_of_france(x) x king_of_france(x) bald(x) bald(x) 285

In ordinary discourse, to avoid the undesirable effect produced by the existential presupposition in (2), we can enrich our utterance with an explanation in the following way: (6) The actual king of France is not bald. There is no actual king of France. The corresponding DRS to (6) must include, however, the existential presupposition and deal with it in the adequate manner, resolving its discourse markers or accommodating it in the corresponding site inside the DRS: (DRS9) [ [ ] [ [ ] bald(x) { [x] king_of_france(x) } ] [ [y] king_of_france(y) ] ] The two possible accommodations for the presupposition in (DRS9), after leaving the possibility of resolution of the marker x aside, are the following ones: (DRS10) [ [x] king_of_france(x) [ [ ] bald(x) ] [ [y] king_of_france(y) ] ] (DRS11) [ [ ] [ [x] bald(x) king_of_france(x) ] [ [y] king_of_france(y) ] ] (DRS10) represents the global accommodation of the presupposition and (DRS11) represents the local accommodation. But, between both options, we must prefer the local accommodation (DRS11), because the global accommodation (DRS10) contains a contradiction since we can resolve the marker y instantiating it in the marker x that appears in an accessible representation. Then, the existential presupposition is cancelled in (DRS11). The addition of van der Sandt s accommodation theory to DRT to deal with presuppositions gives us certain advantages over other alternative theories. It includes, for instance, a resolution mechanism for anaphora we cannot find in the theory of definite descriptions. Moreover, it offers a criterion for distinguishing between different scopes of the presupposition and choosing the most adequate one in each case to cancel it. It also offers the possibility of treating in a different way the different presuppositions appearing in discourse, depending on the relations with their trigger elements and their sites inside the global DRS that represents their meaning. References BEAVER, D. (1997). Presupposition, in BENTHEM, J. van & MEULEN, A. ter (eds.) (1997), Handbook of Logic and Language, North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp.: 939-1008. KAMP, H. & REYLE, U. (1993). From Discourse to Logic, Kluwer, Dordrecht. LEVINSON, S. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. SALGUERO LAMILLAR, F. J. (1994). Anaphoric instantiation problems in an inferential model of utterance representation, in MARTÍN VIDE, C. (ed.) (1994), Current issues in mathematical linguistics, North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp.: 39-48. SANDT, R. van der (1992). Presupposition projection as anaphora resolution. Journal of Semantics, 9: 333-377. SANDT, R. van der (1993). Resolution and accomodation, in KAMP, H. (ed.) (1993), Presupposition, DYANA-2. Dynamic Interpretation of Natural Language. ESPRIT Basic research project 6852. Deliverable R2.2.A, Part II, pp.: 233-242. 286