The Relevance of Equal Splits in Ultimatum Games 1

Similar documents
Entrepreneurial Discovery and the Demmert/Klein Experiment: Additional Evidence from Germany

Learning Lesson Study Course

ECON 484-A1 GAME THEORY AND ECONOMIC APPLICATIONS

When!Identifying!Contributors!is!Costly:!An! Experiment!on!Public!Goods!

An ICT environment to assess and support students mathematical problem-solving performance in non-routine puzzle-like word problems

CHAPTER 5: COMPARABILITY OF WRITTEN QUESTIONNAIRE DATA AND INTERVIEW DATA

Evidence for Reliability, Validity and Learning Effectiveness

Mapping the Assets of Your Community:

CREST Working Paper. Voluntary Provision of Public Goods: The Multiple Unit Case. Mark Bagnoli. Shaul Ben-David Michael McKee

Life and career planning

Kelli Allen. Vicki Nieter. Jeanna Scheve. Foreword by Gregory J. Kaiser

Probability and Game Theory Course Syllabus

OPTIMIZATINON OF TRAINING SETS FOR HEBBIAN-LEARNING- BASED CLASSIFIERS

NCEO Technical Report 27

AP Statistics Summer Assignment 17-18

The Good Judgment Project: A large scale test of different methods of combining expert predictions

GCSE English Language 2012 An investigation into the outcomes for candidates in Wales

Guru: A Computer Tutor that Models Expert Human Tutors

Interactive Whiteboard

BENCHMARK TREND COMPARISON REPORT:

Success Factors for Creativity Workshops in RE

b) Allegation means information in any form forwarded to a Dean relating to possible Misconduct in Scholarly Activity.

Science Fair Project Handbook

Nothing is constant, except change - about the hard job of East German SMEs to move towards new markets

95723 Managing Disruptive Technologies

Aviation English Training: How long Does it Take?

The Federal Reserve Bank of New York

Classroom Assessment Techniques (CATs; Angelo & Cross, 1993)

How do adults reason about their opponent? Typologies of players in a turn-taking game

Keith Weigelt. University of Pennsylvania The Wharton School Management Department 2022 Steinberg-Dietrich Hall Philadelphia, PA (215)

Study Group Handbook

1. Professional learning communities Prelude. 4.2 Introduction

Kindergarten - Unit One - Connecting Themes

While you are waiting... socrative.com, room number SIMLANG2016

Curriculum Design Project with Virtual Manipulatives. Gwenanne Salkind. George Mason University EDCI 856. Dr. Patricia Moyer-Packenham

Why Pay Attention to Race?

Using focal point learning to improve human machine tacit coordination

Tilburg University. Assessing the Efficacy of Gaming in Economics Education Gremmen, Hans; Potters, Jan. Publication date: Link to publication

Hentai High School A Game Guide

The Evolution of Random Phenomena

A Pilot Study on Pearson s Interactive Science 2011 Program

Preprint.

Faculty Schedule Preference Survey Results

Evaluation of Hybrid Online Instruction in Sport Management

TU-E2090 Research Assignment in Operations Management and Services

Critical Thinking in Everyday Life: 9 Strategies

THE WEB 2.0 AS A PLATFORM FOR THE ACQUISITION OF SKILLS, IMPROVE ACADEMIC PERFORMANCE AND DESIGNER CAREER PROMOTION IN THE UNIVERSITY

(I couldn t find a Smartie Book) NEW Grade 5/6 Mathematics: (Number, Statistics and Probability) Title Smartie Mathematics

PREP S SPEAKER LISTENER TECHNIQUE COACHING MANUAL

Swords without Covenants Do Not Lead to Self-Governance* Timothy N. Cason Purdue University. and. Lata Gangadharan Monash University.

Dynamic Evolution with Limited Learning Information on a Small-World Network

Urban Legends Three Week Unit 9th/10th Speech

Scientific Method Investigation of Plant Seed Germination

BEST OFFICIAL WORLD SCHOOLS DEBATE RULES

The Task. A Guide for Tutors in the Rutgers Writing Centers Written and edited by Michael Goeller and Karen Kalteissen

Test How To. Creating a New Test

CHAPTER 4: REIMBURSEMENT STRATEGIES 24

A Study of Metacognitive Awareness of Non-English Majors in L2 Listening

On-the-Fly Customization of Automated Essay Scoring

Undergraduates Views of K-12 Teaching as a Career Choice

Progress Monitoring for Behavior: Data Collection Methods & Procedures

Evidence-based Practice: A Workshop for Training Adult Basic Education, TANF and One Stop Practitioners and Program Administrators

Contents. Foreword... 5

Graduate Division Annual Report Key Findings

Rote rehearsal and spacing effects in the free recall of pure and mixed lists. By: Peter P.J.L. Verkoeijen and Peter F. Delaney

4.0 CAPACITY AND UTILIZATION

Susan K. Woodruff. instructional coaching scale: measuring the impact of coaching interactions

The dilemma of Saussurean communication

Feature-oriented vs. Needs-oriented Product Access for Non-Expert Online Shoppers

CEFR Overall Illustrative English Proficiency Scales

The Use of Statistical, Computational and Modelling Tools in Higher Learning Institutions: A Case Study of the University of Dodoma

WE GAVE A LAWYER BASIC MATH SKILLS, AND YOU WON T BELIEVE WHAT HAPPENED NEXT

Classroom Management that Works: Researched-Based Strategies for Every Teacher By Robert J. Marzano

learning collegiate assessment]

Executive summary (in English)

S T A T 251 C o u r s e S y l l a b u s I n t r o d u c t i o n t o p r o b a b i l i t y

Massachusetts Department of Elementary and Secondary Education. Title I Comparability

EVALUATION OF AN INNOVATIVE SCHOOL EYE HEALTH EDUCATIONAL MODE

Anglia Ruskin University Assessment Offences

An Empirical Analysis of the Effects of Mexican American Studies Participation on Student Achievement within Tucson Unified School District

CSC200: Lecture 4. Allan Borodin

Stacks Teacher notes. Activity description. Suitability. Time. AMP resources. Equipment. Key mathematical language. Key processes

Disambiguation of Thai Personal Name from Online News Articles

Houghton Mifflin Online Assessment System Walkthrough Guide

Concept mapping instrumental support for problem solving

Instructions and Guidelines for Promotion and Tenure Review of IUB Librarians

Strategic Practice: Career Practitioner Case Study

Assessment and Evaluation

Principles of network development and evolution: an experimental study

Session 2B From understanding perspectives to informing public policy the potential and challenges for Q findings to inform survey design

Chapter 4 - Fractions

TD(λ) and Q-Learning Based Ludo Players

CELTA. Syllabus and Assessment Guidelines. Third Edition. University of Cambridge ESOL Examinations 1 Hills Road Cambridge CB1 2EU United Kingdom

Marketing Management

Diagnostic Test. Middle School Mathematics

Education in Armenia. Mher Melik-Baxshian I. INTRODUCTION

Application of Virtual Instruments (VIs) for an enhanced learning environment

Understanding and Interpreting the NRC s Data-Based Assessment of Research-Doctorate Programs in the United States (2010)

Why Misquitoes Buzz in People s Ears (Part 1 of 3)

Transcription:

Games and Economic Behavior 37, 161 169 (2001) doi:10.1006/game.2000.0829, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on The Relevance of Equal Splits in Ultimatum Games 1 Werner Güth 2 Institute for Economic Theory III, Humboldt University Berlin, Spandauer Strasse 1, 10178 Berlin, Germany Steffen Huck 3 Department of Economics, Royal Holloway College, University of London, Egham, Surrey TW20 0EX, United Kingdom and Wieland Müller 4 Department of Economics, Institute for Economic Theory III, Humboldt University Berlin, Spandauer Strasse, 1, 10178 Berlin, Germany Received December 4, 1997; published online August28, 2001 In this note we present a slightly altered version of the mini ultimatum game of G. E. Bolton and R. Zwick (1995, Games Econ. Behav. 10, 95 121). More specifically, we replaced exactly equal splits by nearly equal splits either (slightly) favoring the proposer or the responder. Such a minor change should not matter if behavior was robust. We find, however, a significant change in behavior: Fair offers occur less often when equal splits are replaced by nearly equal splits. Journal of Economic Literature Classification Numbers: C72, C78, C92. 2001 Academic Press Key Words: ultimatum bargaining; fairness; equity. 1. INTRODUCTION The findings on the ultimatum game (see Roth, 1995, for a survey) belong to the most robust experimental results. Bolton and Zwick (1995), 1 We thank Ken Binmore, an anonymous associate editor, and two anonymous referees for helpful comments and suggestions. 2 E-mail: gueth@wiwi.hu-berlin.de. 3 E-mail: s.huck@rhbnc.ac.uk. 4 E-mail: wmueller@wiwi.hu-berlin.de. 161 0899-8256/01 $35.00 Copyright 2001 by Academic Press All rights of reproduction in any form reserved.

162 güth, huck, and müller for example, have shown that essential behavioral regularities like responders willingness to reject unfair offers and proposers propensity to offer equal splits pertain in ultimatum games in which only two offers, a fair and an unfair one, are feasible. Here we investigate such mini ultimatum games in which the fair offer can be slightly unfair. If behavior were robust, such small payoff changes would not matter. But, in fact, they do. Replacing the equal split by a nearly equal split dramatically changes behavior. In particular, the fair outcome is chosen less frequently. We investigated three mini ultimatum games, one similar to Bolton and Zwick and two others in which we replaced the equal split by offers once slightly favoring the proposer and once slightly favoring the responder. We find that proposers are less inclined to make a fair offer if the equal split is replaced by a nearly equal split (especially if the latter slightly favors the responder) while responders reject unfair offers less frequently if both offers favor the proposer. Although these patterns are highly significant they disappear in treatments economizing on subjects, e.g., if the so called strategy method is used. The remainder of the paper is organized as follows: In Section 2 we introduce the experimental design in more detail. In Section 3 we present the main behavioral regularities and Section 4 concludes. 2. EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN The three mini ultimatum games are represented in Fig. 1. First player A chooses between l and r and then, depending on A s choice, player B chooses between L 1 and R 1, respectively, between L 2 and R 2. The three games only differ in the payoffs for the path r L 2. For the variant corresponding to Bolton and Zwick (1995) this path assigns equal payoffs to both players. 5 We refer to this game as Equal. In game Prop player A, the proposer, receives 11 and player B, the responder, gets 9, in case of r L 2. In game Resp this is reversed. (We will refer to the games Prop and Resp also as the inequality games in contrast to the equality game. ) If players are only guided by monetary incentives, the solution of all three games is the unique subgame perfect equilibrium s = l L 1 L 2. The experiments were conducted in summer 1997 and autumn 1999 at Humboldt University. A total of 207 subjects played the one shot 5 The payoff vector ( ) ( 17 h4 1 ) ( h9 1 ) ( 3 corresponds to the payoff vector h = 4 2 h = 3 40 9 2 0 60) of Bolton and Zwick (1995) since ( ) ( 17 3 = 5 3 40 0 60).

the relevance of equal splits 163 FIG. 1. The three games. game(s) (Prop 70, Equal 67, Resp 70). 6 All participants were undergraduates in economics without prior training in game theory, but some basic knowledge of economics. We neither provided any training opportunity before the experiment nor did we repeat the experiment since we are mainly interested in whether small amounts of inequality can change the usually very robust first round behavior in ultimatum games. Translated instructions are provided in Appendix B. An additional 116 subjects played the games using three alternative methods of eliciting choices (see below). 3. RESULTS Table I shows the choices of 207 subjects for standard one shot sequential play. 7 In game Prop proposers roughly choose half and half between l and r. In contrast, in game Equal more than two-thirds of the proposers choose the fair offer r. This is reversed in game Resp, where two-thirds of the proposers pick the unfair offer l. The latter difference is significant at p = 0 002 (χ 2 = 9 72 Pearson). 8 Thus, replacing the equal split by a nearly equal splitmarkedly changes proposer behavior. 6 Ninety-six subjects participated in the experiment conducted in summer 1997, and 111 in the one conducted in autumn 1999 when we replicated the experiment. Since the data sets are very similar we pooled them. 7 Note that the number of proposers exceeds the number of responders. The unmatched proposers were, after the experiment, matched with random responders facing the same proposal. 8 Overall, proposers choose significantly less often the fair offer r when the equal split is replaced. Comparing their behavior in both inequality games with that in the equality game reveals a significantdifference atp = 0 01 (χ 2 = 6 33 Pearson).

164 güth, huck, and müller TABLE I Behavior in All Three Games Decisions Game Proposers Responders l r L 1 R 1 L 2 R 2 Prop 16 20 12 4 17 1 Equal 10 24 4 6 21 2 Resp 24 12 11 11 12 Responder behavior is more difficult to summarize. Virtually all responders accept, of course, the fair offer r. Buthow do responders reactto the unfair offer? Due to sequential play the number of observations here is much smaller than for proposers. Nevertheless, we observe that the rate of rejections is significantly lower in game Prop than in the other two games (p = 0 06, χ 2 = 3 43). We sum up our observations in two behavioral regularities. Regularity 1. Proposers choose more often the unfair offer when the equal splitis replaced by a nearly equal split. This effectis particularly strong when the nearly equal split favors the responder. Regularity 2. Responders rejectunfair offers less often when all agreements imply a payoff advantage for the proposer. How can this sensitivity to slight alterations of a single payoff vector be explained? Looking at the two inequality games separately we get some clues: The data of game Resp suggest that envy dominates fairness concerns (proposers do not want to receive less than their opponent). In contrast, in game Prop proposers may have felt and also be viewed especially strong since all agreements favor them. Proposers may also simply have anticipated Regularity 2. It then makes perfect sense for them to be less afraid of rejections and to choose the greedy offer in game Prop. The results are also in line with a focal point explanation. One might argue that fairness considerations are only triggered if the focal equal split is feasible. Splitting equally plays an important role in our upbringing and, typically, our first bargaining experiences with siblings and friends are situations where sharing equally is quite common (often enforced by third parties like parents or teachers). If the familiar and focal equal split is removed, fairness concerns may notarise.

the relevance of equal splits 165 Next we briefly turn to a methodological question, namely whether one can observe the same behavioral patterns by economizing on subjects using the so called strategy method which forces subjects to choose complete decision plans (strategies). Potentially, this procedure may reveal more information about the motives of a single subject. But there is a caveat as the effects of physical timing are removed 9 and as subjects might be less focussed. 10 A similar problem arises when subjects participate not only in one game butin many games. We have studied the games at hand in a 2 by 2 factorial design (sequential play versus strategy method and one versus many games). Seventy seven additional subjects played one of the games employing the strategy method. 11 In two further treatments, subjects played (at the same time) all three games, 20 participants in the sequential version and 19 in the simultaneous strategic form version. 12 The results are clear cut: Only the natural design, in which subjects play one game sequentially, reveals the behavioral relevance of exactly equal splits. All other designs which economize on subjects fail to produce the same behavioral pattern. 13 This is summarized in Regularity 3. Whereas there are significant differences in behavior across games when only one game is played sequentially there were no differences for all other methods of eliciting choices. Regularity 3 provides further evidence that experimental observations depend crucially on the method of eliciting choices. This was also observed by Schotter et al. (1994) 14 who reporta significantpresenta- 9 Evidence for the relevance of the timing of decisions is provided, for example, by Rapoport (1997) and Güth et al. (1998). 10 Roth (1995, pp. 322 323) who provides a discussion of the pros and cons of the strategy method writes, The obvious disadvantage is that it [the strategy method] removes from experimental observation the possible effects of the timing of decisions in the course of the game. Furthermore, he points out that the strategy method forces subjects to think about each information set in a different way than if they could primarily concentrate on those information sets that arise in the course of the game. He concludes that applying the strategy method amounts to a significant change in the game itself, and argues that there is some need to explore for which kinds of games there may be significant differences in observed behavior when the strategy method is used. 11 Prop 26, Equal 25, Resp 26. 12 For instance, in the first of the two latter treatments, a proposer had to indicate his decisions for each of the three games before his choices were passed on to a responder who, then, had to decide in the corresponding information sets for all three games. 13 The data of the additional treatments are presented in Appendix A. 14 Using a between subjects design, they confronted their subjects with either the normal form (matrix) or the extensive form of a simple game. (Problem 1 in their study is the game most similar to ours.) In either case each subject had exactly two alternative strategies.

166 güth, huck, and müller tion effect for chainstore paradox like games. For instance, the secure strategy of one player was less frequently chosen when subjects were confronted with the extensive rather than with the strategic form of the game. 15 4. DISCUSSION We studied three mini ultimatum games varying only in one payoff vector following the acceptance of the (almost) fair offer. In one version an exactly equal split of the pie was feasible. In two other versions the exactly equal split was replaced by a nearly equal split, once slightly favoring the proposer and once slightly favoring the responder. Comparing the equality game with the inequality games we observed that behavior changed dramatically although the inequality games were generated by only slightly altering a single payoff vector. More precisely, proposers choose significantly more often unfair offers when the exactly equal splitis notfeasible and responders rejectunfair offers less often when all offers imply a payoff advantage for the proposer. The general message of these results (which seem in line with a focal point explanation) is that fairness concerns may be less pronounced in settings where splitting equally is impossible. In reality equal splits are quite often not feasible, e.g., because of different enforceable claims. 16 Finally, our experimental data provide evidence that, in some games, 17 elicitation methods can significantly affect behavior. 15 In our case it seems easy to explain the vanishing differences for the case of players who play all three games simultaneously. There the payoff differences implied by nearly equal splits wash out. (Offering in all three games (nearly) equal splits yields an exactly equal split overall.) With respect to the subjects who play only one game with the strategy method, it seems that we are less sensitive to small payoff differences when imagining their consequences than when actually experiencing them. 16 Also, one mightsuspectthatcooperative behavior, for example, in dilemma games or oligopolies becomes less frequent when the gains from cooperation are asymmetric. Evidence along this line can be found in Mason and Philips (1997) who study duopolies. 17 Brandts and Charness (2000) presentevidence on games in which behavior is robustto elicitation methods.

the relevance of equal splits 167 APPENDIX A.1. Synopsis A. Data of All Treatments TABLE II Proposers Behavior across Games Mode and moves Seq. play Seq. play Sim. play Sim. play one game all games one game all games Game l r l r l r l r Prop 16 20 4 6 9 4 4 5 Equal 10 24 4 6 7 6 3 6 Resp 24 12 5 5 7 6 5 4 50 56 13 17 23 16 12 15 A.2. Detailed Results TABLE III Responders Behavior across Games Mode and moves Seq. play Seq. play Sim. play Sim. play one game all games one game all games Game L 1 R 1 L 2 R 2 L 1 R 1 L 2 R 2 L 1 R 1 L 2 R 2 L 1 R 1 L 2 R 2 Prop 12 4 17 1 2 2 6 8 5 13 6 4 10 Equal 4 6 21 2 2 2 6 8 4 12 7 3 9 1 Resp 11 11 12 2 3 5 10 3 12 1 7 3 10 TABLE IV Results When Subjects Play One Game and Decide Simultaneously Proposer Responder Game l r L 1 L 2 L 1 R 2 R 1 L 2 R 1 R 2 Prop 9 4 7 5 Equal 7 6 7 4 Resp 7 6 9 2 1

168 güth, huck, and müller TABLE V Results When Subjects Play All Three Games and Decide Sequentially (Prop, Equal, Resp) Proposer Responder # r r r =5 # L 2 L 2 L 2 =5 # l l l =4 # R 1 R 1 R 1 =2 # L 1 L 1 L 1 =2 # r r l =1 # L 2 L 2 R 1 =1 TABLE VI Results When Subjects Play All Three Games and Decide Simultaneously (Prop, Equal, Resp) Proposer Responder # r r r =3 # L 1 L 2 L 1 L 2 L 1 L 2 = 5 # l l l =2 # R 1 L 2 R 1 L 2 R 1 L 2 = 2 # r r l =2 # R 1 L 2 L 1 L 2 R 1 L 2 = 1 # l r r =1 # R 1 L 2 R 1 L 2 L 1 L 2 = 1 # l r l =1 # L 1 L 2 L 1 R 2 L 1 L 2 = 1 # r l l =1 B. Translated Instructions Please read the following instructions carefully! In case of questions raise your hand! We will answer all questions privately. Welcome to our experiment! As you will see in a moment you can earn some money. How much depends on whatyou will do and on whatsomebody else with whom you will be randomly matched will do. The rules are quite simple. Look at the following decision tree(s). [Figure(s) of relevantgame tree(s).] (In all three situations) First A decides whether to choose r or l. After A has made his choice, B has to decide. Depending on A s choice, B either has to choose between L1 and R1 or between L2 and R2. Four cases are possible: A chooses l, B chooses L1 : In this case A receives DM 17 and B receives DM 3 (all situations). A chooses l, B chooses R1 : In this case both receive nothing (all situations). A chooses r, B chooses L2 : In this case A receives DM [amount according to game] and B DM [amount according to game]. [In the treatments in which subjects had to decide for all three games, this sentence was repeated for all situations.] A chooses r, B chooses R2 : In this case both receive nothing (all situations). In case you are A, please make your choice between l and r by drawing a small circle around the letter. (Do this for all three situations.)

the relevance of equal splits 169 [Next paragraph only for simultaneous treatments:] In case you are B, please make your choice between L1 and R1 for the case A chooses l and make your choice between L2 and R2 for the case A chooses r. Do this by drawing two (six) circles indicating your decisions. This means that every A has to draw one (three) circle(s) and every B has to draw two (six) circles. [Next paragraph only for sequential treatments:] A s decisions sheet will then be passed to a randomly chosen B. Knowing A s decision B has to make his choice, i.e., if A has chosen l, B has to choose between L1 and R1 ; and if A has chosen r, B has to choose between L2 and R2. As a B do this by drawing a small circle around the label of your choice. (Do this for all three situations!) [Next paragraph only for simultaneous treatments:] After having collected all decision sheets we will pair A s and B s randomly to determine your payoffs. To ensure your anonymity you receive a code number on a separate card. Please write your code number in the appropriate box on your decision sheet and keep your code card. You will receive your payoff only when showing this card. This procedure ensures your anonymity concerning us and the participant you are matched with. You have role [A/B]. REFERENCES Bolton, G. E., and Zwick, R. (1995). Anonymity versus Punishment in Ultimatum Bargaining, Games Econ. Behav. 10, 95 121, doi:10.1006/game.1995.1026. Brandts, J., and Charness, G. (2000). Hot vs. Cold: Sequential Responses and Preference Stability in Experimental Games, Experimental Econ. 2, 227 238. Güth, W., Huck, S., and Rapoport, A. (1998). The Limitations of the Positional Order Effect, J. Econ. Behav. Org. 34, 313 325. Mason, C. F., and Phillips, O. R. (1997). Information and Cost Asymmetry in Experimental Duopoly Markets, Rev. Econ. Stat. 79, 290 299. Roth, A. E. (1995). Bargaining Experiments, in Handbook of Experimental Economics (J. H. Kagel and A. E. Roth, Eds.), pp. 253 348. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press. Rapoport, A. (1997). Order of Play in Strategically Equivalent Games in Extensive Form, Int. J. Game Theory 26, 113 136. Schotter, A., Weigelt, K., and Wilson, C. (1994). A Laboratory Investigation of Multiperson Rationality and Presentation Effects, Games Econ. Behav. 6, 445 468, doi:10.1006/game.1994.1026.