Only elements of K_ are well-formed expressions.

Similar documents
Concept Acquisition Without Representation William Dylan Sabo

Replies to Greco and Turner

CEFR Overall Illustrative English Proficiency Scales

Welcome to the Purdue OWL. Where do I begin? General Strategies. Personalizing Proofreading

Full text of O L O W Science As Inquiry conference. Science as Inquiry

5. UPPER INTERMEDIATE

The Strong Minimalist Thesis and Bounded Optimality

NAME: East Carolina University PSYC Developmental Psychology Dr. Eppler & Dr. Ironsmith

Proof Theory for Syntacticians

The Task. A Guide for Tutors in the Rutgers Writing Centers Written and edited by Michael Goeller and Karen Kalteissen

Critical Thinking in Everyday Life: 9 Strategies

Highlighting and Annotation Tips Foundation Lesson

Life and career planning

MYCIN. The MYCIN Task

Laporan Penelitian Unggulan Prodi

Rubric for Scoring English 1 Unit 1, Rhetorical Analysis

MONTAGE OF EDUCATIONAL ATTRACTIONS

a) analyse sentences, so you know what s going on and how to use that information to help you find the answer.

Correspondence between the DRDP (2015) and the California Preschool Learning Foundations. Foundations (PLF) in Language and Literacy

Writing a composition

Achievement Level Descriptors for American Literature and Composition

Common Core State Standards for English Language Arts

Chapter 9 Banked gap-filling

Notes on The Sciences of the Artificial Adapted from a shorter document written for course (Deciding What to Design) 1

West s Paralegal Today The Legal Team at Work Third Edition

The Effect of Discourse Markers on the Speaking Production of EFL Students. Iman Moradimanesh

Extending Learning Across Time & Space: The Power of Generalization

A Minimalist Approach to Code-Switching. In the field of linguistics, the topic of bilingualism is a broad one. There are many

Tutoring First-Year Writing Students at UNM

Age Effects on Syntactic Control in. Second Language Learning

A Pumpkin Grows. Written by Linda D. Bullock and illustrated by Debby Fisher

DIDACTIC MODEL BRIDGING A CONCEPT WITH PHENOMENA

Grade 4. Common Core Adoption Process. (Unpacked Standards)

Philosophy of Literacy Education. Becoming literate is a complex step by step process that begins at birth. The National

Arizona s English Language Arts Standards th Grade ARIZONA DEPARTMENT OF EDUCATION HIGH ACADEMIC STANDARDS FOR STUDENTS

Statistical Analysis of Climate Change, Renewable Energies, and Sustainability An Independent Investigation for Introduction to Statistics

TRAITS OF GOOD WRITING

LEXICAL COHESION ANALYSIS OF THE ARTICLE WHAT IS A GOOD RESEARCH PROJECT? BY BRIAN PALTRIDGE A JOURNAL ARTICLE

5 th Grade Language Arts Curriculum Map

California Department of Education English Language Development Standards for Grade 8

A process by any other name

The Impact of Honors Programs on Undergraduate Academic Performance, Retention, and Graduation

PAGE(S) WHERE TAUGHT If sub mission ins not a book, cite appropriate location(s))

FOREWORD.. 5 THE PROPER RUSSIAN PRONUNCIATION. 8. УРОК (Unit) УРОК (Unit) УРОК (Unit) УРОК (Unit) 4 80.

Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 146 ( 2014 )

Just in Time to Flip Your Classroom Nathaniel Lasry, Michael Dugdale & Elizabeth Charles

Candidates must achieve a grade of at least C2 level in each examination in order to achieve the overall qualification at C2 Level.

The Effect of Extensive Reading on Developing the Grammatical. Accuracy of the EFL Freshmen at Al Al-Bayt University

Digital Fabrication and Aunt Sarah: Enabling Quadratic Explorations via Technology. Michael L. Connell University of Houston - Downtown

Lecturing Module

Analysis of Enzyme Kinetic Data

GDP Falls as MBA Rises?

ACTION LEARNING: AN INTRODUCTION AND SOME METHODS INTRODUCTION TO ACTION LEARNING

Pedagogical Content Knowledge for Teaching Primary Mathematics: A Case Study of Two Teachers

Listening and Speaking Skills of English Language of Adolescents of Government and Private Schools

Seventh Grade Curriculum

Reading Grammar Section and Lesson Writing Chapter and Lesson Identify a purpose for reading W1-LO; W2- LO; W3- LO; W4- LO; W5-

The Common European Framework of Reference for Languages p. 58 to p. 82

REPORT ON CANDIDATES WORK IN THE CARIBBEAN ADVANCED PROFICIENCY EXAMINATION MAY/JUNE 2012 HISTORY

1 st Quarter (September, October, November) August/September Strand Topic Standard Notes Reading for Literature

Developing a concrete-pictorial-abstract model for negative number arithmetic

Calculators in a Middle School Mathematics Classroom: Helpful or Harmful?

Program Matrix - Reading English 6-12 (DOE Code 398) University of Florida. Reading

Maximizing Learning Through Course Alignment and Experience with Different Types of Knowledge

21st Century Community Learning Center

ELP in whole-school use. Case study Norway. Anita Nyberg

CSC200: Lecture 4. Allan Borodin

Loughton School s curriculum evening. 28 th February 2017

Monitoring Metacognitive abilities in children: A comparison of children between the ages of 5 to 7 years and 8 to 11 years

By Laurence Capron and Will Mitchell, Boston, MA: Harvard Business Review Press, 2012.

PREP S SPEAKER LISTENER TECHNIQUE COACHING MANUAL

Third Misconceptions Seminar Proceedings (1993)

NORTHWESTERN UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF COMMERCE I97

First Grade Curriculum Highlights: In alignment with the Common Core Standards

A non-profit educational institution dedicated to making the world a better place to live

TU-E2090 Research Assignment in Operations Management and Services

Linguistics Program Outcomes Assessment 2012

Anglia Ruskin University Assessment Offences

Ielts listening test practise online. We test you exactly what to practise when you decide to work with a particular listening provider..

Introduction and Motivation

Reviewed by Florina Erbeli

Grade 11 Language Arts (2 Semester Course) CURRICULUM. Course Description ENGLISH 11 (2 Semester Course) Duration: 2 Semesters Prerequisite: None

CUSTOMER EXPERIENCE ASSESSMENT SALES (CEA-S) TEST GUIDE

Intermediate Algebra

Writing for the AP U.S. History Exam

CAAP. Content Analysis Report. Sample College. Institution Code: 9011 Institution Type: 4-Year Subgroup: none Test Date: Spring 2011

EDUCATING TEACHERS FOR CULTURAL AND LINGUISTIC DIVERSITY: A MODEL FOR ALL TEACHERS

Classify: by elimination Road signs

Exploration. CS : Deep Reinforcement Learning Sergey Levine

PART C: ENERGIZERS & TEAM-BUILDING ACTIVITIES TO SUPPORT YOUTH-ADULT PARTNERSHIPS

1 3-5 = Subtraction - a binary operation

A Note on Structuring Employability Skills for Accounting Students

Informatics 2A: Language Complexity and the. Inf2A: Chomsky Hierarchy

WEEK FORTY-SEVEN. Now stay with me here--this is so important. Our topic this week in my opinion, is the ultimate success formula.

Syllabus: INF382D Introduction to Information Resources & Services Spring 2013

ENGBG1 ENGBL1 Campus Linguistics. Meeting 2. Chapter 7 (Morphology) and chapter 9 (Syntax) Pia Sundqvist

ELA/ELD Standards Correlation Matrix for ELD Materials Grade 1 Reading

WHAT ARE VIRTUAL MANIPULATIVES?

University of Pittsburgh Department of Slavic Languages and Literatures. Russian 0015: Russian for Heritage Learners 2 MoWe 3:00PM - 4:15PM G13 CL

Taught Throughout the Year Foundational Skills Reading Writing Language RF.1.2 Demonstrate understanding of spoken words,

Transcription:

PUTNAM'S COMPLAINT Jack K. Horner One of the most acrimoniously disputed issues in contemporary philosophy of language is whether or not, or in what sense, humans may be said to possess an innate language-specific mobilization and acquisition capacity. At the heart of this dispute lies a slogan proponents of linguistic innatism have proclaimed as their credo of war, the so-called "innatist hypothesis" (I.H., for short): the human brain is "programmed" at birth with some quite specific and structured aspects of human natural language; in particular, every linguistically competent human innately possesses a class S of transformational grammars Gi, G2,..., and a function f which assigns weights to elements of this class in a manner modulated by experience. All members of S are held to share certain very general features known as "linguistic universals" such as an activepassive distinction, a transformational component, linguistic categories such as concrete noun, verb taking an abstract subject, and so on. the proponents oflinguistic innatism claim, is virtually unavoidable on any account of linguistic behavior which adequately accounts for both the This hypothesis, existence of linguistic universals and the empirical facts of language acquisition. Several philosophers have balked at accepting the I.H.; indeed, some have found the proposal strong evidence of its proponents' senility.1 Prominent among the movements of this antagonistic requiem is the ubiquitous recitative of Professor Hilary Putnam.2 Yet Putnam's lamentation is, if I am not mistaken, a prelude to a premature burial. For if I understand him correctly, Professor Putnam's arguments do not, for a variety of reasons, succeed in impugning the innatist view. To elaborate this criticism, I will first briefly review several linguistic phenomena which I hold an adequate theory of linguistic behavior must explain; Putnam's remarks will then be assessed against these data. The first datum which an adequate theory of language must be able to explain is what I will call the "creative" aspect of language. Much of what we say or recognize as well-formed parts of language is new to us, in the sense that it is not merely a repetition of anything we have heard before, nor is it, in any important sense, a repetition of patterns we

167 have experienced before. Secondly, it can be shown that the number of sentences which a normal adult user of language can potentially recognize as grammatical is infinite; certain subclasses of English, for example, have been shown to have infinite cardinality. Accordingly, an adequate linguistic theory must account for such a capacity, given the temporally limited resources of the organism. There is only one way that such a capacity could exist, namely, if the structure of language acquisition or recognition could in effect be characterized by a set of recursive rules capable of generating the set of well-formed expressions of the natural language. 3 Thirdly, it is a reasonably well-accepted observation that children acquire a grammar based on very degenerate evidence or reinforcement. For example, many of the expressions they encounter during the language acquisition period are not well-formed: adult speech often contains slurs, false stops, spurious phonemes, and so on. Yet these errors are rejected as such very early in the child's linguistic development. More generally, the linguistic "input" which children receive by the time they may be said to possess linguistic competence does not determine the grammar they actually acquire. This fact can be shown without appealing to elaborate evidence, in the following way. At any given time t Q in a child's life, he will have experienced a finite set K of distinct well-formed expressions E,,...,E of his language. Consider, then, the following very crude grammars: (Rl) (R2) Only elements of K_ are well-formed expressions. Let K be the class consisting of the following <i) E,,..., E «K; (ii) any conjunction of members of K is a member of K Any member of K is we 11-formed. Note first of all that any expression satisfying Rl satisfies R2, but not conversely. This implies that the elements of K_ satisfy both Rl and R2. Hence K Q is not sufficient to determine uniquely a grammar; moreover, the list of rules above can be extended indefinitely.accordingly, any given finite set of expressions satisfies an infinite number of grammatical rules, and thus Kg is not sufficient to determine even a finite class of grammars. Hence an adequate theory

16 8 of linguistic behavior must posit that the determination of grammar in language acquisition involves some feature not implied by the data which the language learner meets. Fourthly, all children in a given language community develop the same grammar, often enough in spite of radically different "inputs." It is quite likely, in fact, that in a given language community, there are children whose "inputs" are disjoint; accordingly, an adequate linguistic theory would have to show how the same grammars can be developed from disjoint data sets. Now any such theory will have to attribute to the language acquisition capacity some feature which is not implied by the elements of the data sets. Finally, all human languages possess the same general form of grammar; in particular all known languages have a transformational rather than a phrase-structure grammar, all have the subject-verb relation, all have quantifiers, and all have proper nouns. I now wish to evaluate Putnam's arguments against the I.H. in light of these data, showing that (1) several of his arguments simply are not cogent; and (2) even if all Putnam's attacks on the I.H. were cogent, they are not all parts of a unified theory of linguistic behavior, and hence, at the very least, constitute a view less coherent than the I.H. According to Putnam, many innatists cite the existence of linguistic universals as evidence in support of the I.H. But surely, he insists, there are accounts explaining the existence of linguistic universals which do not appeal to the existence of some language-specific acquisition capacity. In particular, we might imagine a community of Martians whose innate intellectual equipment is as different from ours as is compatible with their being able to have a language at all. Suppose further that Martian brains are not vastly richer than ours. Accordingly, they will find it possible to employ an infinite set of expressions only if these expressions possess a grammar consisting of a finite set of recursive rules. If the I.H. amounts to nothing more than the assertion Martians must employ a grammar, Putnam argues, then the I.H. could not possibly be false; but of course if that were so, it would not be interesting either. But in any case, we would not have to invoke the existence of a specific set of grammars, S, built in the brain of both Martian and humans to account for

169 the existence of linguistic universals.5 Putnam's objection, then argues that we do not have to invoke the I.H. to show that Martian and natural human languages all have some grammar or other; indeed, the existence of a grammar can be explained strictly by appealing to the need of both kinds of languages to embody a finite set of recursive rules. It must surely be conceded, whatever faults the argument may possess, that the mere existence of grammars for a set of languages does not constitute sufficient grounds for invoking the I.H. But beyond this the claim that the explanation of the existence of some grammar for each language community does not require the I.H. fails to address an important datum. In particular, an adequate theory of linguistic behavior must explain why all human languages possess the same kind of grammar. It is just this very peculiar property of all human grammars that strongly suggests the existence of a universal human grammar, deriving from a source independent of variation in human experience, namely the innate linguistic capacities of men. Hence, that Martian has some grammar and that all human languages have some grammar, and that these two grammars differ, does not in the least impugn the claim advanced by the linguistic innatists. Putnam offers yet another explanation for the existence of linguistic universals. Let us suppose, he says, that language-using human beings evolved independently in two or more places. Then according to the innatist hypothesis, there should be two or more types of human being descended from the two or more original populations, such that normal children of each type would fail to learn the language of the other. Since we do not ever observe such failures, and since there is only one class S built into all human brains, we have to conclude, if the I.H. is true, that language-using involves a sort of evolutionary discontinuity that occurred only once. In that case, however, it is overwhelmingly likely that all human languages are descended from a single original language. But indeed, Putnam counters, the latter is likely even if the I.H. is false, since the human race is generally held to have resulted from a single evolutionary development and since then the human population, initially quite small, spread but slowly. Thus, even if language use were completely learned or invented rather than built in, it is likely that some group of humans first developed language as we know it, and then this language spread to the rest of the world. If all human languages are descended thus from a common parent, then just such highly useful features of the

170 common parent such as quantifiers, proper nouns, and in general, the linguistic universals we in fact observe would be expected to survive. Thus one can explain the existence of linguistic universals merely by appealing to the "common origin" hypothesis, and hence the invocation of the I.H. is merely gratuitous.6 Whatever else may be said about this objection in particular, one must surely agree that the existence of linguistic universals does not constitute conclusive evidence for the I.H. Nevertheless, the objection overlooks a very important feature of linguistic behavior, namely, the transmission of language to children. Since children master the grammar of their language on evidence which fails to determine even a finite class of grammars, it is clear that they must supply, independently of the data, the appropriate grammar or class of grammars for their language. Thus Putnam's "common origin" hypothesis cannot supply an account of language transmission and hence is inadequate. Many innatists claim to derive support for the I.H., Putnam asserts, from the fact that children learn languages with startling rapidity and ease. But surely, he objects, we can account for this phenomenon without appealing to the I.H. More particularly, he argues, it is not surprising that children learn a language as rapidly as they do, because they are constantly exposed to it. In comparison, language teachers claim that students can achieve mastery of a foreign language in 600 hours of direct-method instruction and achieve an incomparably greater vocabulary than that of a young child; by the age of four a child has been exposed to vastly more than 600 hours of direct-method instruction, and so has had plenty of time to acquire even a difficult language.7 But this objection, although illuminating the fact that certain students do acquire mastery of a language in a very brief time, overlooks several important aspects of linguistic behavior. First of all, it is not so clear that learning a second language is analogous in all relevant respects to learning a first language. One might plausibly argue that the acquisition of a second language takes the first as a model of some sort. Since the acquisition of a first language cannot bear this relation to a former language, except on pain of generating an infinite regress, it may be that the acquisition of a second language is considerably easier because of its special relation to the former. However such a suggestion might be evaluated, it is clear that the "second language" argument overlooks, like the previous

171 objections, a very important aspect of linguistic behavior. It was argued above that no amount of data can explicitly determine the acquisition of even the second language. More particularly, none of the grammatical rules found in grammars and none of the rules articulated by teachers of the language are strictly correct. Yet students who master the language do learn the exceptions to the rules. Hence the "second-language" objection just ignores that crucial feature of language learning which allows the acquisition of a grammar on the basis of degenerate evidence, and thus is inadequate to dismiss the I.H. Putnam's final objection to the I.H. is directed against the claim that the capacity for mobilization and acquisition of language is language-specific. If we commit ourselves to the existence of a languagespecific capacity, we must analogously commit ourselves to a mathematics-specific capacity, a puzzle-solving capacity specific to certain puzzles, and so on, because these capacities, too, are not determined completely by the data we receive. But this would be to multiply the "innate" capacities beyond the point of interest or illumination. Rather, the objection goes, it seems much more plausible to attribute the acquisition of language to general, multipurpose learning strategies which are employed in language, mathematics, puzzle-solving, and so on. 8 On close inspection, however, this objection appears to involve several difficulties. First of all, it baldly ignores the fact that nearly all children grasp the same grammar, whereas their puzzle-solving and mathematical competencies differ conspicuously. Thus the evidence for the I.H. is of an importantly different sort than that which one might raise in support of mathematics- and puzzlesolving-specific capacities. Secondly, the objection renders extremely surprising the fact that there are linguistic universals of any sort; and in particular, it renders too surprising the fact that all children in a given language community acquire the same grammar, in spite of diverse and degenerate linguistic data. The above criticisms shield, if correct, the I.H. from Putnam's objections. Nevertheless, I think that even if one assumes that none of these criticisms are cogent, Putnam's view still is less coherent, to say the very least, than the I.H. The I.H., that is, offers a unified, though perhaps daring explanation of the existence of linguistic universals, the amazing rapidity and thoroughness with which children achieve linguistic competence, the "creative" aspect of

172 linguistic behavior, and accounts for the way in which a finite being can possess the power to recognize or potentially produce an infinite number of expressions. In contrast, these features have no comparable unity on Putnam's account. For first of all, the very reason there are linguistic universals of the sort we observe, the I.H. maintains, is just the reason why children are able to learn a grammar on the basis of degenerate evidence. On Putnam's account, in contrast, linguistic universals arose merely because language originated from a single community sharing a common language which contained certain linguistic features bound to be useful in any human social situation; on his view this fact has no connection with the fact that children learn the language based on degenerate evidence. Secondly, on the I.H., the conditions which permit the existence of linguistic universals insure the rapid acquisition of linguistic competence by children. Putnam, in contrast, insists that while the existence of linguistic universals is determined by social utility or the need for a recursive grammar, the rapidity of language acquisition simply comes from great exposure, and nothing more; on this view, then, the ease of language acquisition might be just as great even if there were no linguistic universals. Thirdly, on the I.H. the finite recursive nature of the grammatical rules which the language user acquires is a consequence of the nature of innate linguistic universals; on Putnam's view there is not even an accidental tie between the two. If the choice were mine, then, I would, if Putnam's arguments are the strongest which can be brought against the I.H., cast my lot with the innatist thesis. Putnam's objections show at best, if the above criticism is just, that there will always be non-innatist interpretations of any given linguistic datum. This does not surprise me too greatly: in general, evidence rarely uniquely determines theory. But I believe that no science proceeds by inventing a distinct theory for each distinct datum which seems to fall within its province, as Putnam, by example, suggests we do; rather we seek unified accounts of what we imagine, barring strong objections, to be merely diverse pieces of the same mosaic. Indiana University, Bloomington

173 NOTES ISee in particular Nelson Goodman, "The Epistemological Argument", Synthese 17(1967). 2 Hilary Putnam, "The 'Innateness Hypothesis' and Explanatory Models in Linguistics." In Innate Ideas, ed. by Stephen Stich, California, 1975, pp. 133-14'». 3ln particular, if the language acquisition and production faculties of the organism are such that the class of things acquired or produced can have only finite cardinality, while the class of things acquirable or producible has infinite cardinality, then the structure of language acquisition or production must in effect be characterizable by a set of recursive rules capable of generating the set of well-formed expressions of the natural language. l, More generally, it is a well-known result of elementary model theory that in any metalanguage of a language containing the first-order predicate calculus, the set-theoretic relation "E", sets, and variables ranging over sets, the cardinality of the class of extensionally distinct formation rules satisfiable by a given finite class of expressions in the object language is infinite. 5 Ibid., p. 137. 6 Ibid., p. 140. 7 Ibid., p. 141. 8 Ibid., p. 143.